Skip to main content
Log in

Long-run heterogeneity in an exchange economy with fixed-mix traders

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Economic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We consider an exchange economy where agents have heterogeneous beliefs and assets are long-lived, and investigate the coupled dynamics of asset prices and agents’ wealth. We assume that agents hold fixed-mix portfolios and invest on each asset proportionally to its expected dividends. We prove the existence and uniqueness of a sequence of arbitrage-free market equilibrium prices and provide sufficient conditions for an agent, or a group of agents, to survive or dominate. Our main finding is that long-run coexistence of agents with heterogeneous beliefs, leading to asset prices endogenous fluctuations, is a generic outcome of the market selection process.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8
Fig. 9
Fig. 10

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a list of puzzles and asset pricing anomalies, see, e.g., the entries “Financial Market Anomalies” and “Finance (new developments)” in the New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics.

  2. See however, Cvitanić and Malamud (2011) for a distinction between the price and portfolio impact of a vanishing agent and Cvitanić et al. (2012) for an appraisal of the impact of vanishing agents on cumulated returns.

  3. Heterogeneity may instead be persistent when markets are exogenously incomplete (Blume and Easley 2006; Beker and Chattopadhyay 2010; Coury and Sciubba 2012), when agents have non-tradable labor income (Cao 2013; Cogley et al. 2013), when information is asymmetric and costly (Sciubba 2005), when learning does not converge (Sandroni 2005; Beker and Espino 2011), when agents are ambiguity averse (Condie 2008; Guerdjikova and Sciubba 2015), or when agents have recursive preferences (Borovička 2015; Dindo 2015).

  4. In particular, why should (endogenously determined) prices be easier to forecast than (exogenously given) dividends?

  5. The empirical evidence is that it does not, there were 9520 mutual funds in the USA in 2015.

  6. Bottazzi and Dindo (2014) investigate the same issue in an economy with short-lived assets, finding that the MSH does not generally hold. Bektur (2013) shows that the agent whose rule is the closest, component by component, to the Generalized Kelly rule survives almost surely.

  7. The result seems related to the analysis of the impact of pessimism and optimism on asset prices performed in Jouini and Napp (2010). Note, however, that their result is non-generic in that it holds only when agents’ biases are equal, so that they have the same survival index. See also Blume and Easley (2009). Our results are instead generic.

  8. Note, however, that survival might not be associated with higher welfare (see, e.g., Jouini and Napp 2016).

  9. Given \(\mathbb {R}^S\), \(\varDelta ^S\) denotes its simplex, \(\mathbb {R}^{S}_{+}\) is the subset of vectors with nonnegative components (excluding the null vector), and \(\mathbb {R}^{S}_{++}\) is the subset of vectors with positive components.

  10. The same condition is assumed in the general equilibrium literature that investigates the Market Selection Hypothesis to guarantee existence of a competitive equilibrium (see, e.g., Axiom 3 in Blume and Easley 2006).

  11. This is implied by assuming that agents start with an initial allocation of assets and consumption good.

  12. Evstigneev et al. (2006) establish the result in the more general case of adapted portfolio rules. It is straightforward to see that our proof holds even when beliefs \(\pi ^i_t\) are adapted to the information filtration generated by \(s_{\tau }\) and \(P_{\tau -1}\) for all \(\tau \le t\).

  13. A fourth outcome that might occur in market selection models is path dependency, which arises when each rule has a favorable drift in the limit when it has all the wealth. Horst and Wenzelburger (2008) find path dependency when two competing financial mediators are selected by investors. Bottazzi and Dindo (2014) find path dependency when rules are allowed to depend on prices.

  14. The fact that \(\varPi \subset \varDelta ^S_{+}\) depends on the technical condition \(KL(x^1||x^*)<\mathcal {K}\). Otherwise, the set of rules with relative entropy equal to a given \(x^1\) could encompass rules that are not generated by any belief.

  15. The proposition generalizes to N-agent economies by taking all the possible combinations of the two groups’ effective beliefs.

  16. It remains the difficulty to measure welfare in a framework such ours where rules are not explicitly derived from an utility maximization.

  17. This exercise is in the spirit of Sciubba (2006) where a CAPM-based heuristic rule, a log-optimal rule, and a mean-variance rule, all derived under the truth, are compared.

  18. Dindo (2015) deals with such rules in a general equilibrium model.

  19. Under no aggregate risk, fair pricing holds for each representative agent economy. As a result, all rules coincide when beliefs are homogeneous.

References

  • Alchian, A.: Uncertainty, evolution, and economic theory. J. Polit. Econ. 58, 211–221 (1950)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beker, P.F., Chattopadhyay, S.: Consumption dynamics in general equilibrium: a characterisation when markets are incomplete. J. Econ. Theory 145, 2133–2185 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beker, P.F., Espino, E.: The dynamics of efficient asset trading with heterogeneous beliefs. J. Econ. Theory 146, 189–229 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bektur, Ç.: Performance of investment strategies in the absence of correct beliefs. Decis. Econ. Finance 36(1), 23–37 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bhamra, H., Uppal, R.: Asset prices with heterogeneity in preferences and beliefs. Rev. Financ. Stud. 27, 519–580 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blume, L., Easley, D.: Evolution and market behavior. J. Econ. Theory 58, 9–40 (1992)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blume, L., Easley, D.: If you are so smart why aren’t you rich? Belief selection in complete and incomplete markets. Econometrica 74, 929–966 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blume, L., Easley, D.: The market organism: Long-run survival in markets with heterogenous traders. J. Econ. Dyn. Control 33, 1023–1035 (2009)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borovička, J.: Survival and long-run dynamics with heterogeneous beliefs under recursive preferences. Working paper, New York University (2015)

  • Bottazzi, G., Dindo, P.: Evolution and market behavior with endogenous investment rules. J. Econ. Dyn. Control 48, 121–146 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bottazzi, G., Dindo, P.: Drift criteria for persistence of discrete stochastic processes on the line. LEM Working Paper 2015-26, Sant’Anna School for Advanced Studies, Pisa (2015)

  • Cao, D.: Speculation and financial wealth distribution under belief heterogeneity. Econ. J. (2017). doi:10.1111/ecoj.12519

  • Cogley, T., Sargent, T., Tsyrennikov, V.: Wealth dynamics in a bond economy with heterogeneous beliefs. Econ. J. 124, 1–30 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Condie, S.: Living with ambiguity: prices and survival when investors have heterogeneous preferences for ambiguity. Econ. Theory 36, 81–108 (2008). doi:10.1007/s00199-007-0264-1

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coury, T., Sciubba, E.: Belief heterogeneity and survival in incomplete markets. Econ. Theory 49, 37–58 (2012). doi:10.1007/s00199-010-0531-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cvitanić, J., Jouini, E., Malamud, S., Napp, C.: Financial markets equilibrium with heterogeneous agents. Rev. Finance 16(1), 285–321 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cvitanić, J., Malamud, S.: Price impact and portfolio impact. J. Financ. Econ. 100(1), 201–225 (2011)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dindo, P.: Survival in speculative markets. LEM Working Paper 2015-32, Scuola Superiore Sant’Anna, Pisa (2015)

  • Epstein, L., Zin, S.: Substitution, risk aversion, and the temporal behavior of consumption and asset returns: a theoretical framework. Econometrica 57, 937–969 (1989)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evstigneev, I., Hens, T., Schenk-Hoppé, K.: Market selection of financial trading strategies: global stability. Math. Finance 12, 329–339 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evstigneev, I., Hens, T., Schenk-Hoppé, K.: Evolutionary stable stock markets. Econ. Theory 27, 449–468 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evstigneev, I., Hens, T., Schenk-Hoppé, K.: Globally evolutionary stable portfolio rules. J. Econ. Theory 140, 197–228 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evstigneev, I., Hens, T., Schenk-Hoppé, K.: Evolutionary finance. In: Hens, T., Schenk-Hoppé, K. (eds.) Handbook of Financial Markets: Dynamics and Evolution. North-Holland (Handbooks in Economics Series) (2009)

  • Fedyk, Y., Heyerdahl-Larsen, C., Walden, J.: Market selection and welfare in a multi-asset economy. Rev. Finance 17(3), 1179–1237 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M.: Essays in Positive Economics. Univ. Chicago Press, Chicago (1953)

    Google Scholar 

  • Guerdjikova, A., Sciubba, E.: Survival with ambiguity. J. Econ. Theory 155, 50–94 (2015)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hens, T., Schenk-Hoppé, K.: Handbook of Financial Markets: Dynamics and Evolution. North-Holland (Handbooks in Economics Series) (2009)

  • Horst, U., Wenzelburger, J.: On non-ergodic asset prices. Econ. Theory 34, 207–234 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jouini, E., Napp, C.: Heterogeneous beliefs and asset pricing in discrete time: an analysis of pessimism and doubt. J. Econ. Dyn. Control 30(7), 1233–1260 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jouini, E., Napp, C.: Consensus consumer and intertemporal asset pricing with heterogeneous beliefs. Rev. Econ. Stud. 74(4), 1149–1174 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jouini, E., Napp, C.: Unbiased disagreement in financial markets, waves of pessimism and the risk-return trade-off. Rev. Finance 15(3), 575–601 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jouini, E., Napp, C.: Live fast, die young. Economic Theory 62, 265–278 (2016). doi:10.1007/s00199-015-0894-7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, J.: A new interpretation of information rates. Bell Syst.Tech. J. 35, 917–926 (1956)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lucas, R.: Asset prices in an exchange economy. Econometrica 46(6), 1429–1445 (1978)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Massari, F.: Markets with heterogeneous beliefs: a necessary and sufficient condition for a trader to vanish. J. Econ. Dyn. Control 78, 190–205 (2017)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandroni, A.: Do markets favor agents able to make accurate predictions. Econometrica 68(6), 1303–1341 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandroni, A.: Efficient markets and Bayes’ rule. Econ. Theory 26, 741–764 (2005). doi:10.1007/s00199-004-0567-4

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sciubba, E.: Asymmetric information and survival in financial markets. Econ. Theory 25, 353–379 (2005). doi:10.1007/s00199-003-0434-8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sciubba, E.: The evolution of portfolio rules and the capital asset pricing model. Econ. Theory 29, 123–150 (2006). doi:10.1007/s00199-005-0013-2

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taussky, O.: A recurring theorem on determinants. Am. Math. Mon. 56, 672–676 (1949)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yan, H.: Natural selection in financial markets: Does it work? Manag. Sci. 54, 1935–1950 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pietro Dindo.

Additional information

We wish to thank the editor, the associate editor, and two anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments and suggestions. Pietro Dindo gratefully acknowledges the support of the Marie Curie International Outgoing Fellowship PIOF-GA-2011-300637 within the 7th European Community Framework Programme and the hospitality of the Department of Economics at Cornell University. Daniele Giachini gratefully acknowledges the hospitality of the Department of Banking and Finance at the University of Zurich.

Proofs of Theorems and Lemmas

Proofs of Theorems and Lemmas

1.1 Proof of Lemma 1

Let \(\bar{\alpha }=\max _{i\in N, k\in K} \{\alpha ^i_k\}\) and \(\bar{\delta }=\max _{i \in N} \{ \sum _{k=1}^K \alpha ^i_k\}\). Consider the matrix \(A(W;\alpha )\) in (9) whose element \(A_{k,l}\) reads

$$\begin{aligned} A_{k,l}=\frac{\sum \nolimits _{i=1}^N\alpha ^i_k\alpha ^i_l W^i}{\sum \nolimits _{j=1}^N \alpha ^j_l W^j}\,. \end{aligned}$$

From \(\mathbf{R1}\) and \(\mathbf{R2}\), it follows that \(0<A_{k,l}<\bar{\alpha }<1\) for all kl, and that \(0< \sum _{k=1}^K \, A_{k,l}< \bar{\delta } < 1\) for all l. The first group of inequalities implies

$$\begin{aligned} \left| \mathbb {I}-A \right| _{l,l}- \sum _{k=1,k\ne l}^K \, \left| \mathbb {I}-A \right| _{k,l}= \sum _{k=1}^K \, \left( \mathbb {I}-A \right) _{k,l}\,, \end{aligned}$$

while the second group implies \(\sum _{k=1}^K \, \left( \mathbb {I}-A \right) _{k,l}=1-\sum _{k=1}^K \, A_{k,l}>1-\bar{\delta }>0\). Thus, the matrix \(\mathbb {I}-A\) is column strictly diagonally dominant and, by the Levy–Desplanques theorem (Taussky 1949), invertible.

1.2 Proof of Proposition 1

The first part of the statement follows from Lemma 1 and from the derivation in the text before the proposition.

Regarding the absence of arbitrages consider the following. According to Stiemke’s Lemma, the absence of arbitrage is equivalent to the existence of a vector \(q \in \mathbb {R}^S_{++}\) such that \(R(W; \alpha , D) q = P\) or, with (12),

$$\begin{aligned} D q =(\mathbb {I}- A(W; \alpha ))P= \left[ \begin{matrix} 1-\frac{\sum \limits _{i=1}^N\alpha ^i_1\alpha ^i_1 W^i}{\sum \limits _{j=1}^N \alpha ^j_1 W^j} &{}\cdots &{} -\frac{\sum \limits _{i=1}^N\alpha ^i_1\alpha ^i_K W^i}{\sum \limits _{j=1}^N \alpha ^j_K W^j}\\ \vdots &{} \ddots &{}\vdots \\ -\frac{\sum \limits _{i=1}^N\alpha ^i_K\alpha ^i_1 W^i}{\sum \limits _{j=1}^N \alpha ^j_1 W^j} &{} \cdots &{} 1-\frac{\sum \limits _{i=1}^N\alpha ^i_K\alpha ^i_K W^i}{\sum \limits _{j=1}^N \alpha ^j_K W^j} \end{matrix} \right] \left[ \begin{matrix} \sum \limits _{j=1}^N \alpha ^j_1 W^j\\ \vdots \\ \vdots \\ \sum \limits _{j=1}^N \alpha ^j_K W^j \end{matrix} \right] . \end{aligned}$$

Thus, the kth component of \((\mathbb {I} - A(W; \alpha ))P\) reads \(\sum _{i=1}^{N}[(1-\delta ^i) \delta ^i W^i]x_k^i\). By \(\mathbf{R1}\) it is \(x^i_k=\sum _{s=1}^S\pi ^i_s d_{k}(s)\); hence, one has

$$\begin{aligned} D q =D \left[ \begin{matrix} \sum \nolimits _{i=1}^{N}[(1-\delta ^i) \delta ^i W^i]\pi _1^i\\ \vdots \\ \sum \nolimits _{i=1}^{N}[(1-\delta ^i) \delta ^i W^i]\pi _S^i \end{matrix} \right] . \end{aligned}$$

That is, calling \(q_s\) the sth component of q and given that D has full rank by \(\mathbf{D4}\), it is \(q_s=\sum _{i=1}^{N}[(1-\delta ^i) \delta ^i W^i]\pi ^i_s\). \(\mathbf{R1}\), \(\mathbf{R2}\), and the first part of the Proposition imply \(q_s>0\) \(\forall s\in S\) so that the statement is proven.

1.3 Proof of Propositions 2

As we shall show, the stochastic process that corresponds to the two groups’ relative wealth dynamics has bounded increments. As a result, we can prove the proposition by applying Theorem 2.1 in Bottazzi and Dindo (2015).

Consider the variable

$$\begin{aligned} z^I_t=\log \frac{w^I_t}{1-w^I_t} \end{aligned}$$
(25)

such that \(z^I_t=z^I_{t-1}+ g^I(\sigma _t)\), with \(g^I(\sigma _t)=\log G^I(\sigma _t)\) and

$$\begin{aligned} G^I(\sigma _t)= \frac{\sum _{k=1}^{K} r_{k,s_t}(w_{t-1};x,\delta ,D) \beta ^I_{k}(w_{t-1};x)}{\sum _{k=1}^{K} r_{k,s_t}(w_{t-1};x,\delta ,D) \beta ^{I^c}_{k}(w_{t-1};x)} \;. \end{aligned}$$
(26)

One has the following.

Lemma 5

The process \(z^I_t\) has bounded increments, that is, there exists a \(B \in \mathbb {R}\) such that \(|z^I_t-z^I_{t-1}|<B\) \({{\mathrm{P}}}\)-a.s..

Proof

By \(\mathbf{R3}\) there exists a small enough \(\varepsilon >0\) such that \(\varepsilon \le x^i_{k}\le 1-\varepsilon \) \(\forall \,i,k\). Since

$$\begin{aligned} \beta ^I_k(w_t;x)=\frac{x^I_k(w_t;x)}{\sum _{i=1}^N x^i_k w^i_t}\,, \end{aligned}$$

for any asset k and any time t it is

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\varepsilon }{1-\varepsilon } \le \beta ^I_k(w_t;x)\le \frac{1-\varepsilon }{\varepsilon }\,. \end{aligned}$$

Consider the matrix

$$\begin{aligned} r_{k,s}(w_{t};x,\delta ,D)= & {} [(1-\delta )(\mathbb {I}-\delta A(w_{t};x))^{-1} \, D]_{k,s}\\= & {} (1-\delta )d_{k,s}+\delta p_{k,s}(w_{t};x,\delta ,D)\,. \end{aligned}$$

It holds: \(0<r_{k,s}(w_{t};x,\delta ,D)<1\) \(\forall k,t,s\) and \(\sum _{k=1}^K r_{k,s}(w_{t};x,\delta ,D)=1\) \(\forall s,t\). Thus for any group I, state s and time t one has

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\varepsilon }{1-\varepsilon } \le \sum \limits _{k=1}^{K}r_{k,s}(w_{t};x,\delta ,D)\beta ^I_k(w_t;x) \le \frac{1-\varepsilon }{\varepsilon }\;. \end{aligned}$$

Given (25) and (26), by direct algebraic substitution it is straightforward to verify that

$$\begin{aligned} 2\log \frac{\varepsilon }{1-\varepsilon }\le z^I_{t}-z^I_{t-1} \le 2\log \frac{1-\varepsilon }{\varepsilon } \end{aligned}$$

and the statement is proven. \(\square \)

In order to prove Proposition 2, use the notation of Bottazzi and Dindo (2015) and call \(\mu _t(z^I)\) the date t conditional drift of the process \(\{z^I_t\}\), \(\mu _t(z^I)={{\mathrm{E}}}^{{{\mathrm{P}}}}[z^I_{t+1}-z^I_t | \mathfrak {I}_t, z^I_t=z^I]\). If \(\mu ^I(w;v)\) is an element of the set \(\{ \mu ^I(w) | w\in \varDelta ^N,w^I=v\}\), with \(\mu ^I(w)\) defined in (19), then by construction

$$\begin{aligned} \mu _t(z^I)=\mu ^I\left( w_t;\,v=\frac{e^{z^I}}{1+e^{z^I}}\right) . \end{aligned}$$

Having fixed \(z^I\), and thus v, the precise value of \(w_t\) still depends on the specific element of \(\mathfrak {I}_t\) considered.

We shall start from the proof of statement (i). If \(\underline{\mu }^I(0) > 0\), then, given the property of the lower bound and the continuity of \(\mu ^I(w;v)\) with respect to v, there exist \(\varepsilon >0\) and \(M>0\) such that, for all \(z^I<-M\) and t, it is \(\mu _t(z^I)>\varepsilon \). Since \(z^I_t\) has bounded increments, Theorem 2.1 in Bottazzi and Dindo (2015) applies and \({{\mathrm{Prob}}}{\{\limsup _{t\rightarrow \infty } z^I_t > -\infty \}}=1\). Provided \(\overline{\mu }^I(1) > 0\), the same reasoning applies to prove (ii), see also Corollary 2.1 of Bottazzi and Dindo (2015).

1.4 Proof of Lemma 2

Let us consider the process \(z_t^I\) in (25) and all the other quantities defined at the beginning of appendix A.3. We begin with the following Lemma.

Lemma 6

If the set of rules are not overlapping, \(\mathbf{R4}\), and if there are no redundant assets, \(\mathbf{D4}\), then \(z_t^I\) does not possess any deterministic fixed point, that is, \(\not \exists \;z\) s.t. \( P (z^I_t=z|z^I_{t'}=z)=1\) \(\forall t>t'\).

Proof

Suppose such z exists and at a certain time \(t-1\) it is \(z^I_{t-1}=z\). Then, by definition, it holds that \(z^I_{t}-z^I_{t-1}=0\) for all the possible states of the world \(s=1,2,...,S\), so that

$$\begin{aligned} \sum \limits _{k=1}^{K} r_{k,s}(w_{t-1};x,\delta ,D)\left( \beta ^I_{k}(w_{t-1};x)-\beta ^{I^c}_{k}(w_{t-1};x)\right) =0 \quad \forall s=1,2,...,S\;. \end{aligned}$$

That is

$$\begin{aligned} \left( \beta ^{I}(w_{t-1};x)-\beta ^ {I^c}(w_{t-1};x)\right) \, \left( (\mathbb {I}-\delta A(w_{t-1};x))^{-1} D\right) = \varvec{0} \;. \end{aligned}$$

The trivial solution \(\beta ^I=\beta ^{I^c}\) is excluded by \(\mathbf{R4}\), and according to Proposition 1, the kernel of \((\mathbb {I}-\delta A(w_{t-1},x))^{-1}D\) is zero, implying that the system of equations has no solution and the statement is proven. \(\square \)

The proof proceeds by noticing that \(G^I\) in (26) depends on history \(\sigma _t\) through the wealth distribution \(w_t\) and the last realized state \(s_t\). Given the distribution \(w \in \varDelta ^{N}\) define

$$\begin{aligned} \bar{G}^I(\sigma _t)=\max _{s=1,\ldots ,S} \{|G^I(w,s_t)|\}\;, \end{aligned}$$

which, being the upper envelope of continuous functions, is a continuous function on the compact set \(\varDelta ^{N}\). Then, by the Weierstrass theorem, it has a minimum \(\underline{G}\). Moreover, it is \(\underline{G}>0\) because, otherwise, \(z^I_t\) would have a deterministic fixed point, which is not possible by Lemma 6. Then

$$\begin{aligned} {{\mathrm{Prob}}}\left\{ |z^i_{t}-z^i_{t-1}|\ge \underline{g} \,|\,\mathfrak {I}_{t-1}\right\} \ge \rho =\min \{\pi _1,\ldots ,\pi _S\}. \end{aligned}$$

and by taking \(\gamma = {\min \lbrace \underline{g},\rho \rbrace }/{2}\) the assertion is proven.

1.5 Proof of Lemma 3

Let us consider the first statement. If it is wrong, then

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{w^{I^c}_{t+1}}{w^{I^c}_{t}}-\frac{w^{I}_{t+1}}{w^{I}_{t}}= \sum \limits _{k=1}^{K} \left( \beta ^{I^c}_k(w_{t};x)-\beta ^{I}_k(w_{t};x)\right) \, r_{k,s}(w_{t};x,\delta ,D)\ge 0 \quad \forall s \end{aligned}$$
(27)

and, since the process does not admit any deterministic fixed point (c.f. Lemma 6), the inequality is strict for some \(s^\prime \). By construction it is

$$\begin{aligned} \sum \limits _{k=1}^{K} \left( \beta ^{I^c}_k(w_{t};x)-\beta ^I_k(w_{t};x)\right) p_{k,t} = 0\,. \end{aligned}$$

Together with (27) the latter implies that \(\beta ^{I^c}(w_{t};x)-\beta ^I(w_{t};x)\) would be a weak arbitrage, which contradicts the hypotheses. For the second statement one can reason following the same lines and, in order to complete the proof, it is enough to choose \(\epsilon =\min _s\{\pi _s\}/2\).

1.6 Proof of Proposition 3

Consider the process \(z^I_t\) in (25) and all the other quantities defined at the beginning of appendix A.3. Then we can directly apply Lemma 5 and \(z^I_t\) has bounded increments. \(\mathbf{R4}\) and the lack of arbitrages imply by Lemma 3

$$\begin{aligned} {{\mathrm{Prob}}}{\left\{ z^I_{t+1}-z^I_t> 0\, \Big | \,\mathfrak {I}_t\right\} }= & {} {{\mathrm{Prob}}}{\left\{ \frac{w^I_{t+1}}{w^{I^c}_{t+1}}> \frac{w^{I}_{t}}{w^{I^c}_{t}}\, \Big | \,\mathfrak {I}_t\right\} }\\= & {} {{\mathrm{Prob}}}{\left\{ \frac{w^I_{t+1}}{w^{I}_{t}}> \frac{w^{I^c}_{t+1}}{w^{I^c}_{t}}\, \Big | \,\mathfrak {I}_t\right\} }>\epsilon \,. \end{aligned}$$

Moreover, invoking Lemma 2, one has

$$\begin{aligned} {{\mathrm{Prob}}}\left\{ \left| z^I_{t+1}-z^I_t\right|>\gamma \Big | \mathfrak {I}_{t}\right\} ={{\mathrm{Prob}}}\left\{ \left| \log \frac{w^I_{t+1}}{w^{I^c}_{t+1}}-\log \frac{w^{I}_{t}}{w^{I^c}_{t}}\right|>\gamma \, \Bigg | \mathfrak {I}_{t}\right\} > \gamma \,. \end{aligned}$$

Thus, defining \(\epsilon _L=\min \{\epsilon ,\gamma \}/2\), one gets \({{\mathrm{Prob}}}\{z^I_{t+1}>z^I_t+\epsilon _L\,| \mathfrak {I}_{t}\}>\epsilon _L\), meaning that the process \(z^I_t\) has finite positive increments. A symmetric argument shows that \(z^I_t\) has also negative finite increments.

We shall start from the proof of statement (i) and (ii). Using the notation of Bottazzi and Dindo (2015), we call \(\mu _t(z^I)\) the date t conditional drift of \(\{z^I_t\}\), \(\mu _t(z^I)={{\mathrm{E}}}^{{{\mathrm{P}}}}[z^I_{t+1}-z^I_t | \mathfrak {I}_t, z^I_t=z^I]\). If \(\mu ^I(w;v)\) is an element of the set \(\{ \mu ^I(w) | w\in \varDelta ^N,w^I=v\}\), with \(\mu ^I(w)\) defined in (19), then by construction

$$\begin{aligned} \mu _t(z^I)=\mu ^I\left( w_t;\,v=\frac{e^{z^I}}{1+e^{z^I}}\right) \,. \end{aligned}$$

Having fixed \(z^I\), and thus v, the precise value of \(w_t\) still depends on the specific element of \(\mathfrak {I}_t\) considered.

By continuity of \(\mu ^I(w;v)\) with respect to v and by the definition of lower bound, the conditions \(\underline{\mu }^I(0) > 0\) and \(\underline{\mu }^I(1) > 0\) imply that there exist \(\varepsilon >0\) and \(M>0\) such that, for any t, it is \(\mu _t(z^I)>\varepsilon \) if \(z^I>M\) or \(z^I<-M\). Using Theorem 3.1 from Bottazzi and Dindo (2015), it follows that \({{\mathrm{Prob}}}{\{\lim _{t\rightarrow \infty } z^I_t = +\infty \}}=1\), group I dominates. Conversely, conditions \(\overline{\mu }^I(0) < 0\) and \(\overline{\mu }^I(1) <0\) imply that there exist \(\varepsilon >0\) and \(M>0\) such that, for any t, it is \(\mu _t(z^I)<-\varepsilon \) if \(z^I>M\) or \(z^I<-M\). Using Corollary 3.1 of Bottazzi and Dindo (2015), it follows that \({{\mathrm{Prob}}}{\{\lim _{t\rightarrow \infty } z^I_t = -\infty \}}=1\) and group I vanishes.

In order to prove statement (iii) note that, by Proposition 2, we already know that both groups survive. Thus, we need to prove that for \(G=I, I^c\)

$$\begin{aligned} {{\mathrm{Prob}}}\{\liminf _{t \rightarrow \infty } w^G_{t} = 0\,\, \text {and} \,\,\limsup _{t \rightarrow \infty } w^G_{t} = 1\}=1\,. \end{aligned}$$

Assume by contradiction that for a group G

$$\begin{aligned} {{\mathrm{Prob}}}\{\liminf _{t \rightarrow \infty } w^G_{t} = 0\,\, \text {and} \,\,\limsup _{t \rightarrow \infty } w^G_{t} = 1\}<1\,. \end{aligned}$$

Then, there must exist a positive measure set \(\varSigma ' \subset \varSigma \) such that for all \(\sigma \in \varSigma '\)

$$\begin{aligned} \liminf _{t \rightarrow \infty } w^G_{t}(\sigma )> 0\,\, \text {or} \,\,\limsup _{t \rightarrow \infty } w^G_{t}(\sigma ) < 1\,. \end{aligned}$$

The latter is in contradiction with the process \(\{z^I_t\}\) having finite positive and negative increments.

1.7 Proof of Corollary 2

Consider the group formed by agent i alone, where \(\pi ^i=\pi \), and call \(\mu ^i(w;v)\) a generic element of the set \(\{ \mu ^i(w) | w\in \varDelta ^N,w^i=v\}\). When \(v=1\) agent i owns all the wealth and normalized prices correspond to her portfolio rule. Thus, from (19) one gets

$$\begin{aligned} \mu ^i(w;1)=-\sum \limits _{s=1}^S\pi _s\log \left( \delta +(1-\delta )\sum \limits _{k=1}^K d_{k,s}\frac{x^{i^c}_k(w,x)}{x^i_k}\right) , \end{aligned}$$

where \(x^{i^c}(w,x)\) is the aggregate portfolio rule of all the agents different from i. From the strict convexity of the function \(-\log (\cdot )\) and by the fact that agent i has correct beliefs, one has

$$\begin{aligned} \mu ^i(w;1)>-\log \left( \delta +(1-\delta )\sum \limits _{k=1}^K \left( \sum \limits _{s=1}^S\pi _sd_{k,s}\right) \frac{x_k^{i^c}(w,x)}{x_k^i}\right) =0, \end{aligned}$$

where in the latter we have used the definition of Subjective Generalized Kelly rule, \(\mathbf{R1}\). This immediately implies \(\underline{\mu }^i(1)>0\).

Now consider the case \(v=0\), one has

$$\begin{aligned} \mu ^i(w;0)=\sum \limits _{s=1}^S\pi _s\log \left( \sum \limits _{k=1}^K\frac{r_{k,s}(w;x,\delta ,D)}{x_k^{i^c}(w,x)} x^i_k\right) , \end{aligned}$$

where \(r_{k,s}(w;x,\delta ,D)\) is the ks element of the normalized payoff matrix \(r(w;x,\delta ,D)\). To prove that \(\underline{\mu }^i(0)>0\), we show that \(\mu ^i(w;0)>0\) for any admissible w. First, we prove that \(\lim _{\delta \rightarrow 0}\mu ^i(w;0)>0\), and then we show that \(\lim _{\delta \rightarrow 1}\mu ^i(w;0)=0\).

For the first step one has

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \mu ^i(w;0)}{\partial \delta }= & {} \sum \limits _{s=1}^S\pi _s\left( \sum \limits _{k=1}^K\frac{r_{k,s}(w;x,\delta ,D)}{x^{i^c}_k(w,x)}x^i_k\right) ^{-1}\\&\left( \sum \limits _{k=1}^K \frac{x^i_k}{x^{i^c}_k(w,x)} \frac{\partial r_{k,s}(w;x,\delta ,D)}{\partial \delta }\right) . \end{aligned}$$

Its sign depends upon the derivative of the payoff matrix with respect to \(\delta \). Using matrix differentiation, it reads

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial r(w;x,\delta ,D)}{\partial \delta }= & {} -(\mathbb {I}-\delta A(w;x))^{-1}D\\&-(1-\delta )(\mathbb {I}-\delta A(w;x))^{-1} A(w;x) (\mathbb {I}-\delta A(w;x))^{-1}D\,, \end{aligned}$$

and implies \(\partial r_{k,s}(w;x,\delta ,D)/\partial \delta <0\) for any ks.

For the second step, we use that \(r_{k,s}(w;x,\delta ,D)=(1-\delta )\,d_{k,s}+\delta \, p_{k,s}(w;x,\delta ,D)\). Call p the matrix whose ks element is \(p_{k,s}(w;x,\delta ,D)\). Let us rewrite equation (10) in terms of normalized quantities, it reads

$$\begin{aligned} (\mathbb {I}-\delta A(w;x)) p=(1-\delta )A(w;x)D\,. \end{aligned}$$

Thus in the limit of \(\delta \rightarrow 1\) every column of p, call it \(p_s\), solves the system

$$\begin{aligned} (\mathbb {I}-A(w;x))p_s=\mathbf{0}\,, \end{aligned}$$

which can be written as \(A(w;x)p_s=p_s\). Notice that, given w with \(w^i=0\), for each s \(p_s=x^{i^c}(w,x)\) is a possible solution of the system. Moreover, since \(\sum \limits _{k=1}^K |A_{k,j}(w;x)|=1\) \(\forall j\) implies that A(wx) is a contraction, by Banach fixed point theorem such solution is unique. Thus,

$$\begin{aligned} \lim _{\delta \rightarrow 1}\mu ^i(w;0)=\sum \limits _{s=1}^S\pi _s\log \left( \sum \limits _{k=1}^K\frac{x_k^{i^c}(w,x)}{x_k^{i^c}(w,x)}x^i_k\right) =0\,. \end{aligned}$$

Concluding we have shown that \(\underline{\mu }^i(1)>0\) and \(\underline{\mu }^i(0)>0\), hence by point (i) of Proposition 3 agent i dominates and the Corollary is proven.

1.8 Proof of Lemma 4

From the definition of conditional drift

$$\begin{aligned} \mu (0)= & {} \sum \limits _{s=1}^{S}\pi _s\log \left( \delta +(1-\delta )\sum \limits _{k=1}^{K}d_{k,s}\frac{x^1_k}{x^2_k}\right) \quad \text {and} \quad \\ \mu (1)= & {} -\sum \limits _{s=1}^{S}\pi _s\log \left( \delta +(1-\delta )\sum \limits _{k=1}^{K}d_{k,s}\frac{x^2_k}{x^1_k}\right) . \end{aligned}$$

Considering that \(0\le d_{k,s} \le 1\) for all sk and that \(\sum _{k=1}^{K}d_{k,s}=1\) for all s, we have

$$\begin{aligned} \mu (0)>(1-\delta )\sum \limits _{s=1}^{S}\pi _s\log \left( \sum \limits _{k=1}^{K}d_{k,s}\frac{x^1_k}{x^2_k}\right) \ge (1-\delta )\sum \limits _{k=1}^{K}x^*_k \log \left( \frac{x^1_k}{x^2_k}\right) \end{aligned}$$

and at the same time

$$\begin{aligned} \mu (1)<-(1-\delta )\sum \limits _{s=1}^{S}\pi _s\log \left( \sum \limits _{k=1}^{K}d_{k,s}\frac{x^2_k}{x^1_k}\right) \le (1-\delta ) \sum \limits _{k=1}^{K}x^*_k \log \left( \frac{x^1_k}{x^2_k}\right) . \end{aligned}$$

Putting together the two inequalities proves the assertion.

1.9 Proof of Proposition 4

The statement follows from the particular case of Proposition 3 when \(N=2\) together with Lemma 4 and the definition of normalized prices.

1.10 Proof of Corollary 3

The proof of the survival of agent 1 follows from Lemma 4 and Proposition 4. When agent 1 beliefs are correct, so that \(x^1=x^*\), she also dominates since, exploiting the strict convexity of \(-\log (\cdot )\),

$$\begin{aligned} \mu (1)&=\sum _s \pi _s \left( -\log \left( \delta +(1-\delta )\sum _{k=1}^{K} d_{k,s} \frac{x^2_k}{x^*_k}\right) \right) >\\&\quad \,\,-\log \left( \delta +(1-\delta )\sum _{k=1}^{K}\frac{x^2_k}{x^*_k}\sum _s\pi _s d_{k,s}\right) \\&=-\log \left( \delta +(1-\delta )\sum _{k=1}^{K}\frac{x^2_k}{x^*_k}x^*_k\right) =0\,. \end{aligned}$$

1.11 Proof of Proposition 5

The statement follows from the properties of the function \(KL(x||x^*)\,:\,\varDelta ^K\rightarrow \mathbb {R}_+,\,x\mapsto KL(x||x^*) \). In particular, it is a continuous strictly convex function with a minimum equal to zero in \(x=x^*\). Thus, it is defined over the compact set \(\partial (\bar{\varDelta })\) and there exists a minimum over this set because of the Weierstrass theorem. The strict convexity of \(KL(x||x^*)\) implies that it is also strictly quasi convex. This property together with the fact that \(x^*\in \bar{\varDelta }\) implies \(\{x\,:\,KL(x||x^*)<\mathcal {K}\}\subseteq \bar{\varDelta }\). Hence, it is possible to choose a \(\pi ^1\ne \pi \) such that \(KL(x^1||x^*)=m<\mathcal {K}-\epsilon \) with \(\epsilon >0\) and small enough. Then, one can easily define the set \(\varPi =\{\pi '\,:\,\pi '\in \varDelta ^S_{+},\, KL(x'||x^*)=m\}\) which has always at least two elements. Choosing \(x^1\) and \(x^2\) such that \(\pi ^1,\pi ^2\in \varPi \) it is \(\nabla _{x^*}(x^2||x^1)=0\).

1.12 Proof of Proposition 6

An asset market economy with agents trading according to Subjective Generalized Kelly rules and an asset market economy with agents maximizing expected log-utilities under effective beliefs have, by construction, the same relative wealth dynamics. When markets are dynamically complete and agents maximize an expected log-utility, there is no loss of generality, assuming that they are trading all possible contingent commodities in date zero. In fact, all asset structures, as long as they are complete, allow agents to achieve the same consumption allocation, so that the relative wealth dynamics does not depend upon the asset structure. Under time-zero trading, it is well known that agents allocate in each state contingent good a fraction of wealth proportional to the state likelihood. In a two-agent economy, the relative wealth dynamics can thus be rewritten as

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{w^1_{t+1}(\sigma _{t},s_{t+1})}{w^2_{t+1}(\sigma _{t},s_{t+1})} = \frac{\hat{\pi }^1_{s_{t+1}}(w_t;\delta ,D)}{\hat{\pi }^2_{s_{t+1}}(w_t;\delta ,D)} \frac{w^1_t(\sigma _t)}{w^2_t(\sigma _t)} \quad \forall \sigma _t, s_{t+1}, t\,. \end{aligned}$$

Applying the definition of the conditional drift \(\mu (\cdot )\) to the log of the above process leads to the result.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bottazzi, G., Dindo, P. & Giachini, D. Long-run heterogeneity in an exchange economy with fixed-mix traders. Econ Theory 66, 407–447 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-017-1066-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-017-1066-8

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation