Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Do we value mobility?

  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Is there a trade-off between people’s preference for income equality and income mobility? Testing for the existence of such a trade-off is difficult because mobility is a multifaceted concept. We analyse results from a questionnaire experiment based on simple precise concepts of income inequality and income mobility. We find no direct trade-off in preference between mobility and equality, but an indirect trade-off, applying when more income mobility can only be obtained at the expense of some income inequality. Mobility preference—but not equality preference—appears to be driven by personal experience of mobility.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Prais (1955), Rogoff (1953), Duncan (1966), Goldthorpe (1980), Conlisk (1990).

  2. For welfare approaches see Atkinson (1981), Atkinson and Bourguignon (1982), Chakravarty et al. (1985), Dardanoni (1993), Gottschalk and Spolaore (2002), Markandya (1982); for axiomatic approaches see Shorrocks (1978), Cowell (1985), Cowell and Flachaire (2011), Fields and Ok (1996), Mitra and Ok (1998), D’Agostino and Dardanoni (2009).

  3. See Gaertner and Schokkaert (2012), the seminal articles by Yaari and Bar-Hillel (1984), Amiel and Cowell (1992) and the overviews in Amiel (1999) and Konow (2003). For complementary studies using the experimental method see e.g., Traub et al. (2005), Krawczyk (2010), and Cappelen et al. (2010).

  4. Underlying the liberal position is the view that identifies income mobility with equality of opportunity (Stokey 1998, p. 161). However “ equality of opportunity” has a variety of interpretations: it is used in the egalitarian literature to describe a situation of procedural equality of opportunity (Rawls 1971) or to represent the ideal of an egalitarianism tempered by responsibility (Dworkin 1981; Roemer 1998).

  5. The term ‘Great Gatsby’ curve was used for the first time by Krueger (2012), in a speech delivered to the Center for American Progress. The evidence is the subject of lively debate: for some, the curve simply rejects on empirical grounds the idea that income inequality is acceptable as long as there is income mobility, since it shows that “more inequality of income in the present is likely to make family background play a stronger role in determining the adult outcome of young people” (Corak 2013); for others, the evidence is “neither particularly surprising nor suggestive of any specific conclusions or policy recommendations” (Mankiw 2013), since it only reflects different degrees of heterogeneity in the ability of people of different countries.

  6. This is consistent with David Hume and Adam Smith who argued that the sympathy and impartiality required to discuss distributive justice can only be obtained by putting some distance between the social decision maker and the persons whose welfare is to be evaluated (Bernasconi 2002; Bosmans and Schokkaert 2004; Amiel et al. 2009; Konow 2009).

  7. Negative association, where \(0.5<m\le 1\), is only of theoretical interest since real world mobility data never show complete reversal between parents and children’s economic positions; see Dardanoni et al. (2012) who show that the hypothesis of nonnegative association cannot be rejected in almost all social mobility tables in 149 different countries and time periods.

  8. For example, Shorrocks (1978) developed an axiomatic approach to mobility measurement where an axiom is explicitly introduced which assigns maximum value to transition matrices (a reduced form of mobility tables which do not give information on the marginal distributions) with “the least amount of predictability”. Dardanoni (1993) presents a model where children coming from parents in lower economic positions receive a higher weight in the social evaluation than those coming from better positioned families: as he restricts attention to tables with non-negative dependence, it follows that welfare is maximised, ceteris paribus, by mobility tables with origin independence. Gottschalk and Spolaore (2002) also develop a framework where a specific form of inequality aversion restricted to the children’s generation is shown to induce a strict preference for independence.

  9. See Field and Ok’s (1999) remark about Friedman (1962).

  10. There are views that value neither equality nor mobility: according to Nozick (1974), any inequality that has not been obtained by expropriation or exploitation can be justified.

  11. Gaertner and Schokkaert (2012) argue that in some cases students may also represent a specifically interesting subgroup of the population to focus on since they may be seen as the future economic and political elite of the country and therefore in the position to affect actual economic and social policy.

  12. Even with regards to the role of incentives in experimental economics there is however some debate; see Camerer and Hogarth (1999), for a classical article on the issue.

  13. “Impartial position” means that the individual whose preferences are considered “ is not directly involved in the distributions of income in the society” . This was explained in the introduction to the questionnaire, which also explained other features, including the fact that the questionnaire is about “ social preferences for the distributions of incomes in hypothetical societies of two generations, the generation of the parents and the generation of the children” ; the fact “ there are different dimensions which may be involved in considering income distributions” ; the way in which displays have to be looked at and interpreted. The full questionnaire is available at http://darp.lse.ac.uk/resources/questionnaires/MobilityQuestionnaireWelfare

  14. In general, previous questionnaires conducted to investigate people’s attitude towards income inequality took the form of a test of the classical Pigou-Dalton principle of transfers (Amiel and Cowell 1992, 1998; Harrison and Seidl 1994; Bernasconi 2002; Traub and Schmidt 2009). Support for the principle depends on the range of the income distribution in which income transfers occur, on the type of verbal or numerical test conducted, on the frames adopted to test it (e.g. whether from a external observer viewpoint, under a condition similar to the “veil of ignorance”, or under one of individual risk)—Amiel (1999), Gaertner and Schokkaert (2012).

  15. This can be verified comparing the proportions of answers of type (B,A) in (Q2,Q8) and (Q5,Q8), with those of type (A,B) which are consistent with an opposite tendency. While the proportions of the latter patterns are very small, the former are larger, with differences that are statistically significant. In particular, in (Q2,Q8) the proportion of answers (B,A) is 8.5 % (30/355) and those of type (A,B) is 3.7 % (13/355) (\(d=2.76\), one-tailed \(p<1\,\%\)); in (Q5,Q8) the answers (B,A) are 5.9 % (21/355) and those of type (A,B) is 2.3 % (8/355) (\(d=2.6\), one-tailed \(p<1\,\%\)). Instead, there is no significance difference in the frequencies of (A,B) and (B,A) answers in (Q2,Q5).

  16. An alternative hypothesis here is that people do not switch preferences between the three questions, and in particular that they choose in Q3 and Q6 the same scenario A as in Q8. For example, a prediction of “no trade-off ” would hold either for individuals who do not care about mobility, or for those who consider the greater inequality of scenario B in the three questions anyhow too high to be compensated for any amount of mobility (even when mobility is perfect as in B of Q3).

  17. For the aggregate sample the increases in response B are: \(+\)23.2 % (35.4–11.2 % \(=\) 126/353–40/355) between Q6 and Q8 (\(d=6.597\), one-tailed \( p<1\,\%\)); \(+\)39.0 % (49.2–11.2 % \(=\) 159/356–40/355) between Q3 and Q8 (\(d=8.365\), one-tailed \(p<1\,\%\)); \(+\)13.8 % (49.2–35.4 % \(=\) 159/356–126/353) between Q3 and Q6 (\(d=1.896\), one-tailed \(p<5\,\%\));

  18. As above, in order to determinate the statistical significance of patterns (BA), they can be contrasted with the symmetric patterns (A, B). The comparison show that: in (Q3, Q6), category (B, A) corresponds to 15.6 % (55/352) versus 7.7 % (27/352) of (A, B) (\(d=3.20\), one-tailed \(p<1\,\%\)); in (Q3, Q8) answers (BA) are 31.9 % (113/354) and those (A, B) are 3.1 % (8/354) (\(d=9.25\), one-tailed \(p<1\,\%\)); in (Q6, Q8), (BA) count for 22.1 % (78/352) and (A, B) for 3.7 % (13/352) (\(d=6.92\), one-tailed \(p<1\,\%\)).

    Table 7 Distributions of answers in (Q3,Q6), (Q3,Q8), (Q6,Q8)
  19. As is well known, an even stronger attitude for mobility associated with lower preferences for income equality has been especially found in non-European Anglo-Saxon countries like the US, Australia and New Zealand (Alesina and Ferrara 2005; Alesina and Giuliano 2011).

  20. Indeed, most of the literature on diverse ethnicity and social mobility has focused on the effect of belonging to certain social classes and attitudes toward out-groups and how mobility may affect and may be affected by this relationships, for example for the impact that immigrants may have for the degree of mobility in a society and from here the attitude towards ethnic out-groups between different social classes. There are also studies that have investigated preferences for redistribution between immigrants. An interesting finding here is that the effect of the culture of the country of origin is stronger on attitudes towards redistribution than the effect of the characteristics of the country of destination (Luttmer and Singhal 2011).

  21. It is nevertheless worthwhile to remark that there is no significant correlation between family income (F1) and the nationality of the respondents (A1), see the correlation matrix in the Appendix (not even within the UK sample where the correlation is \(-\)0.069).

  22. Supporting this interpretation note the negative effect of “ prospect on social position” (P2) rather than the “ prospect on income” (P1), which also has a negative effect. Removing P2 from the regression makes P1 not significant.

  23. The regression obviously reports the difference between Israel and the UK; the difference between Italy and the UK remains statistically significant (at \(p\approx 0.02\)).

References

  • Alesina A, La Ferrara E (2005) Preferences for redistribution in the land of opportunities. J Public Econ 89:897–931

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alesina A, Giuliano P (2011) Preferences for redistribution. In: Benhabib J, Jackson MO, Bisin A (eds) Handbook of social economics, vol 1A. North Holland, Amsterdam, The Netherlands

    Google Scholar 

  • Alesina A, Giuliano P (2013) Family ties. NBER Working Paper No. 18966

  • Amiel Y (1999) The subjective approach to the measurement of income inequality. In: Silber J (ed) Handbook on income inequality measurement. Kluwer, Dewenter

    Google Scholar 

  • Amiel Y, Cowell FA (1992) Measurement of income inequality: experimental test by questionnaire. J Public Econ 47:3–26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amiel Y, Cowell FA (1998) Distributional orderings and the transfer principle: a re-examination. Res Econ Inequal 8:195–215

    Google Scholar 

  • Amiel Y, Cowell FA (1999) Thinking about inequality. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Amiel Y, Cowell FA, Gaertner W (2009) To be or not to be involved: a questionnaire-experimental view on Harsanyi’s utilitarian ethics. Soc Choice Welf 32:299–316

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson AB (1970) On the measurement of inequality. J Econ Theory 2:244–263

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson AB (1981) The measurement of economic mobility. In Essays in honour of Jan Pen

  • Atkinson AB, Bourguignon F (1982) The comparison of multidimensional distributions of economic status. Rev Econ Stud 49:183–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartels L (2005) Homer gets a tax cut: inequality and public policy in the American mind. Perspect Polit 3:15–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benabou R, Ok E (2001) Social mobility and the demand for redistribution: the POUM hypothesis. Q J Econ 116:447–487

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernasconi M (2002) How should income be divided? Questionnaire evidence from the theory of impartial. J Econ 9:163–195

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bosmans K, Schokkaert E (2004) Social welfare, the veil of ignorance and purely individual risk: an empirical examination. Res Econ Inequal 11:85–114

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Breen R, Luijkx R (2004) Social mobility in Europe between 1970 and 2000. In: Breen R (ed) Social mobility in Europe. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer CF, Hogarth RM (1999) The effects of financial incentives in experiments: a review and capital-labor-production framework. J Risk Uncertain 19:7–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen AW, Sorensen EO, Tungodden B (2010) Responsibility for what? Fairness and individual responsibility. Eur Econ Rev 54:429–441

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravarty SR, Dutta B, Weymark J (1985) Ethical indices of income mobility. Soc Choice Welf 2:1–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Checchi D, Ichino A, Rustichini A (1999) More equal but less mobile? J Public Econ 74:351–393

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conlisk J (1990) Monotone mobility matrices. J Math Sociol 15:173–191

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corak M (2013) Income inequality, equality of opportunity, and intergenerational mobility. J Econ Perspect 27:79–102

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corneo G, Grüner H-P (2002) Individual preferences for political redistribution. J Public Econ 83:83–107

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cowell FA (1985) Measures of distributional change: an axiomatic approach. Rev Econ Stud 52:135–151

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cowell FA, Flachaire E (2011) Measuring mobility. Public Economics Discussion Paper 8, STICERD, London School of Economics, London WC2A 2AE

  • D’Agostino M, Dardanoni V (2009) The measurement of rank mobility. J Econ Theory 144:1783–1803

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dardanoni V (1993) Measuring social mobility. J Econ Theory 61:372–394

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dardanoni V, Fiorini M, Forcina A (2012) Stochastic monotonicity in intergenerational mobility tables. J Appl Econom 27:85–107

  • Duncan O (1966) Methodological issues in the analysis of economic mobility. In: Smelser N, Lipset S (eds) Social structure and mobility in economic development. Aldine, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin R (1981) What is equality? Part 2: equality of resources. Philos Public Affairs 10:283–345

    Google Scholar 

  • Erikson R, Goldthorpe JH (1992) The constant flux. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Esping-Andersen G (1999) Social foundations of postindustrial economies. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Falk A, Heckman JJ (2009) Lab experiments are a major source of knowledge in the social sciences. Science 326:535–538

  • Fields GS, Ok EA (1996) The meaning and measurement of income mobility. J Econ Theory 71:349–377

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fields GS, Ok EA (1999) The measurement of income mobility: an introduction to the literature. In: Silber J (ed) Handbook on income inequality measurement. Kluwer, Dewenter

    Google Scholar 

  • Fong C (2001) Social preferences, self-interest and the demand for redistribution. J Public Econ 82:225–246

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Formby JP, Smith WJ, Zheng B (2004) Mobility measurement, transition matrices and statistical inference. J Econom 120:181–205

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (1962) Capitalism and freedom. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaertner W, Schokkaert E (2012) Empirical social choice: questionnaire-experimental studies on distributive justice. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Galor O, Moav O (2006) Das human kapital: a theory of the demise of the class structure. Rev Econ Stud 73:85–117

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Georgiadis A, Manning A (2012) Spend it like Beckham? Inequality and redistribution in the UK. 1983–204. Public Choice 151:537–563

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldthorpe J (1980) Social mobility and class structure in modern Britain. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Gottschalk P, Spolaore E (2002) On the evaluation of economic mobility. Rev Econ Stud 69:191–208

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harrison E, Seidl C (1994) Perceptional inequality and preferential judgements: an empirical examinationof distributional judgments. Public Choice 79:61–81

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirschman AO (1973) The changing tolerance for income inequality in the course of economic development (with a mathematical appendix by Michael Rothschild). Q J Econ 87:544–566

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Isaksson AS, Lindskog A (2009) Preferences for redistribution—a cross-country study in fairness. J Econ Behav Organ 72:884–902

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Konow J (2003) Which is the fairest one of all? A positive analysis of justice theories. J Econ Lit 41: 1188–1239

  • Konow J (2009) Is fairness in the eye of the beholder? An impartial spectator analysis of justice. Social Choice Welf 33:101–127

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krawczyk M (2010) A glimpse through the veil of ignorance: equality of opportunity and support for redistribution. J Public Econ 94:131–141

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krueger A (2012) The rise and consequences of inequality in the US. Presentation to the Center for American Progress, January 12th. (http://www.americanprogress.org/events/2012/01/12/17181/the-rise-and-consequences-of-inequality/)

  • Kuziemko I, Norton MI, Saez E, Stantcheva S (2013) How elastic are preferences for redistribution? Evidence from randomized survey experiment. NBER Working Paper Series, n. 18865

  • Loury G (1981) Intergenerational transfers and the distribution of earnings. Econometrica 49:843–867

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luttmer EFP, Singhal M (2011) Culture, context, and the taste for redistribution. Am Econ J 3:157–179

    Google Scholar 

  • Mankiw G (2013) Observations on the great gatsby curve. Article published on Greg Mankiw’s Blog. (http://gregmankiw.blogspot.nl/2013/07/some-observations-on-great-gatsby-curve.html)

  • Markandya A (1982) Intergenerational exchange mobility and economic welfare. Eur Econ Rev 17:301–324

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitra T, Ok EA (1998) The measurement of income mobility: a partial ordering approach. Econ Theory 12:77–102

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick R (1974) Anarchy, state and utopia. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • OECD (2011) Divided we stand: why inequality keeps rising. OECD Publishing, Paris

  • Olivera J (2013) Preferences for redistribution in Europe. GINI Discussion Paper 67

  • Piketty T (1995) Social mobility and redistributive politics. Q J Econ 110:551–583

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prais S (1955) Measuring social mobility. J R Stat Soc Ser A 118:56–66

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1971) A theory of justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts

    Google Scholar 

  • Roemer J (1998) Equality of opportunity. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Rogoff N (1953) Recent trends in occupational mobility. Free Press, Glencoe

    Google Scholar 

  • Shorrocks AF (1978) The measurement of mobility. Econometrica 46:1013–1024

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stokey N (1998) Shirtsleeves to shirtsleeves: the economic of social mobility. In: Schwartz NL, Jacobs D, Kalai E (eds) Frontiers of research in economic theory: the Nancy L. Schwartz memorial lectures 1983–1997. Econometric Society Monographs, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Traub S, Seidl C, Schmidt U, Levati M (2005) Friedman, Harsanyi, Rawls, Boulding—or somebody else? An experimental investigation of distributive justice. Social Choice Welf 24:283–309

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Traub S, Schmidt U (2009) An experimental study on individual choice, social welfare, and social preferences. Eur Econ Rev 53:385–400

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van de gaer D, Schokkaert E, Martinez M (2001) Three meanings of intergenerational mobility. Economica 68:519–537

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yaari M, Bar-Hillel M (1984) On dividing justly. Social Choice Welf 1:1–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We thank Anat Alexandron, Latika Sharma and Yinfei Dong for research assistance. Michele Bernasconi gratefully acknowledges partial support from the Swiss & Global - Ca’ Foscari Foundation. We especially thank the reviewers and the editor for several comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Valentino Dardanoni.

Appendix

Appendix

See Table 11.

Table 11 Correlation matrix for controls

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Amiel, Y., Bernasconi, M., Cowell, F. et al. Do we value mobility?. Soc Choice Welf 44, 231–255 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-014-0839-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-014-0839-2

Keywords

Navigation