Skip to main content
Log in

Normative decision analysis in forensic science

  • Published:
Artificial Intelligence and Law Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper focuses on the normative analysis—in the sense of the classic decision-theoretic formulation—of decision problems that arise in connection with forensic expert reporting. We distinguish this analytical account from other common types of decision analyses, such as descriptive approaches. While decision theory is, since several decades, an extensively discussed topic in legal literature, its use in forensic science is more recent, and with an emphasis on goals such as the analysis of the logical structure of forensic expert conclusions regarding, for example, propositions of common source of evidential and known materials. Typical examples are so-called identification (or, individualization) decisions, especially categorical conclusions according to which fingermarks (or stains of biological nature, handwriting, etc.) come from a particular a person of interest. We will present and compare ways of stating forensic identification decisions in decision-theoretic terms and explain their underlying rationale. In particular, we will emphasize the importance of viewing this analysis as normative in the sense of providing a reflective rather than a prescriptive reference point against which people in charge of forensic identification decisions may compare their otherwise (possibly) intuitive and informal reasoning, before acting. Normative decision analysis in forensic science thus provides a vector through which current practice can be articulated, scrutinized and rethought.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. An illustrative example for this is the recent ICAIL 2017 workshop Evidence & Decision Making in the Law—Theoretical, Computational and Empirical Approaches (The 16th International Conference on Artificial Intelligence and Law, June 16 2017, King’s College, London) which covered contributions to help make progress in our understanding of the following topics:

    1. “1.

      Modeling evidential reasoning and decision making at trial (e.g. evidence weighing; conflict resolution; standards of proof and rules of decision);

    2. 2.

      Evidence-based decision making and the architecture of the trial system (e.g. rules of admissibility; discovery procedures; adversary v. inquisitorial models; rules of weight v. free proof); and

    3. 3.

      The role and limitations of expected utility theory, and more generally cost/benefit analysis, for evidence-based decision making.”*

    *https://icail2017evidencedecision.wordpress.com/cfp/ (last accessed Aug 31 2018).

  2. We use here the term expected value theory in a generic sense, as a synonym for classic decision theory, introduced in a non-technical way in Sect. 2. It is understood that the term ‘value’ may be replaced, for example, by the notions of utility or loss, depending on the area of application.

  3. In forensic science, the term individualization is commonly understood as the reduction of a pool of potential donors of a forensic trace (e.g., an impression, a mark or physical matter) to a single source, which may be an object or a person (Champod 2000).

  4. Non-identification is understood here not as ‘exclusion’, but as an unspecified alternative covering all situations other than ‘identification’.

  5. It is assumed here that this probability is also informed by any relevant evidence E bearing on H that may be available to the decision-maker at the time of the decision. Thus, one’s decision is preceded by inference based on available evidence. This inferential step, commonly dealt with probabilistically (Aitken and Taroni 2004), is not covered here, and \(\Pr (H_{1}{\mid }E, I)\) is written more shortly as \(\Pr (H_{1}{\mid }I)\).

  6. Note that the provision of a norm does not imply prescription. See also Sect. 5.2 on the notion of conditional advice.

  7. Note that this is different for the minimax criterion mentioned in Sect. 4.1 which involves no computation, only a direct comparison between losses of decision consequences.

  8. It is possible to understand this term as the prior odds or the posterior odds for the propositions of interest. The latter is the product of the prior odds and the likelihood ratio for any data considered relevant (e.g., Parmigiani 2001).

  9. It is also possible to interpret the magnitudes as the probabilities and the length of the levers as the losses of adverse decision consequences. See Biedermann et al. (2016a) for further discussion.

  10. The value of empowering individual decision-makers in various societal positions and functions is also recognised in areas beyond the law. An example for this in philosophy of politics is Mondadori who has been quoted as saying “[w]e can say that—given the importance of decisions in one’s every day life—it is a matter of democracy to have the opportunity to be supported by logical mechanisms for formal analysis of information.” (D’Agostino et al. 2001, p. 11)

  11. Note that SWGFAST evolved to what currently is the Subcommittee on Friction Ridge, which is part of the Organization of Scientific Area Committees (OSAC), administered by National Institute of Standards and Technology (NIST).

  12. The term ‘decision’ is also systematically used in a recent report issued by the AAAS (Thompson et al. 2017).

  13. The ‘value of findings’ is also sometimes referred to as the ‘weight of evidence’, that is an expression of the way and the extent to which particular (scientific) results help to discriminate between competing propositions of interest (e.g., Willis et al. 2015).

  14. Note that the quote from the DFSC announcement considers the terms likelihood and probability as synonyms which, strictly speaking, is not correct from a statistical point of view.

References

  • Aitken CGG, Taroni F (2004) Statistics and the evaluation of evidence for forensic scientists, 2nd edn. Wiley, Chichester

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aitken CGG, Roberts P, Jackson G (2010) Fundamentals of probability and statistical evidence in criminal proceedings (practitioner guide no. 1), guidance for judges, lawyers, forensic scientists and expert witnesses, Royal Statistical Society’s Working Group on Statistics and the Law. www.rss.org.uk/Images/PDF/influencing-change/rss-fundamentals-probability-statistical-evidence.pdf

  • Allen RJ (2003) The error of expected loss minimization. Law Probab Risk 2:1–7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen RJ (2015) A note to my philosophical friends about expertise and legal systems. HumanaMente J Philos Stud 28:71–86

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen RJ, Pardo MS (2018) Relative plausibility and its critics. Technical report 3179601, The University of Alabama School of Law. https://ssrn.com/abstract=3179601

  • Anderson T, Schum DA, Twining W (2005) Analysis of evidence, 2nd edn. Law in Context, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Baron J (2008) Thinking and deciding, 4th edn. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron J (2012) The point of normative models in judgment and decision making. Front Psychol 3:577

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger JO (1985) Statistical decision theory and Bayesian analysis, 2nd edn. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bernardo JM, Smith AFM (2000) Bayesian theory, 2nd edn. Wiley, Chichester

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Biedermann A, Bozza S, Taroni F (2008) Decision theoretic properties of forensic identification: underlying logic and argumentative implications. Forensic Sci Int 177:120–132

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biedermann A, Taroni F, Aitken C (2014) Liberties and constraints of the normative approach to evaluation and decision in forensic science: a discussion towards overcoming some common misconceptions. Law Probab Risk 13:181–191

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biedermann A, Bozza S, Taroni F (2016a) The decisionalization of individualization. Forensic Sci Int 266:29–38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Biedermann A, Bozza S, Taroni F, Aitken C (2016b) Reframing the debate: a question of probability, not of likelihood ratio. Sci Justice 56:392–396 (Special Issue on Measuring and Reporting the Precision of Forensic Likelihood Ratios)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broeders T (2009) Decision-making in the forensic arena. In: Kaptein H, Prakken H, Verheij B (eds) Legal evidence and proof, statistics, stories, logic. Ashgate Publishing, Farnham, pp 71–92

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchak L (2016) Decision theory. In: Hájek A, Hitchcock C (eds) Oxford handbook of probability and philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 789–814

    Google Scholar 

  • Champod C (2000) Identification/individualisation, overview and meaning of ID. In: Siegel JH, Saukko PJ, Knupfer GC (eds) Encycl Forensic Sci. Academic Press, San Diego, pp 1077–1084

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Champod C, Lennard C, Margot P, Stoilovic M (2016) Fingerprints and other ridge skin impressions, 2nd edn. CRC Press, Boca Raton

    Google Scholar 

  • Chondros TG (2010) Archimedes’ influence in science and engineering. In: Paipetis S, Ceccarelli M (eds) The genius of Archimedes-23 centuries of influence on mathematics, science and engineering, history of mechanism and machine science 11. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 411–425

    Google Scholar 

  • Cole SA (2014) Individualization is dead, long live individualization! Reforms of reporting practices for fingerprint analysis in the United States. Law Probab Risk 13:117–150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Agostino M, Giorello G, Veca S (2001) “Ragionare dobbiamo, e spesso”. In: D’Agostino M, Giorello G, Veca S (eds) Logica e politica, per Marco Mondadori, il Saggiatore, Milano, pp 11–14

  • de Finetti B (1961) Dans quel sens la théorie de la décision est-elle et doit-elle être “normative”. In: Colloques Internationaux du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, “La Decision”. Éditions du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, Paris, pp 159–169

  • de Finetti B (1974) Theory of probability, a critical introductory treatment, vol 1. Wiley, London

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • de Finetti B (2017) Theory of probability, a critical introductory treatment, reprint edn. Wiley, Chichester

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dijksterhuis EJ, Dikshoorn C, Knorr WR (1987) Archimedes. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hastie R (1993) Algebraic models of juror decision making. In: Hastie R (ed) Inside the juror. The psychology of juror decision making. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 84–115

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan J (1968) Decision theory and the factfinding process. Stanf Law Rev 20:1065–1092

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaye DH (1999) Clarifying the burden of persuasion: what Bayesian decision rules do and do not do. Int J Evid Proof 3:1–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kotsoglou KN (2013) How to become an epistemic engineer: what shifts when we change the standard of proof? Law Probab Risk 12:275–298

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindley DV (1985) Making decisions, 2nd edn. Wiley, Chichester

    Google Scholar 

  • Luce RD, Raiffa H (1958) Games and decisions: introduction and critical survey. Wiley, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Parmigiani G (2001) Decision theory: Bayesian. In: Smelser N, Baltes P (eds) International encyclopedia of social and behavioral sciences. Elsevier, Oxford, pp 3327–3334

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Raiffa H (1968) Decision analysis. Introductory lectures on choices under uncertainty. Addison-Wesley, Reading

  • Raiffa H, Schlaifer R (1961) Applied statistical decision theory. The M.I.T. Press, Cambridge

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Savage LJ (1951) Theory of statistical decision. J Am Stat Assoc 46:55–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage LJ (1972) The foundations of statistics, 2nd edn. Dover, New York

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Schum DA (1994) Evidential foundations of probabilistic reasoning. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith JQ (1988) Decision analysis: a Bayesian approach. Chapman and Hall, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Stoney DA (2012) Discussion on the paper by Neumann, Evett and Skerrett. J R Stat Soc Ser A (Stati Soc) 175:399–400

    Google Scholar 

  • SWGFAST (2013) Guideline for the articulation of the decision-making process for the individualization in friction ridge examination, ver. 1.0. https://www.nist.gov/sites/default/files/documents/2016/10/26/swgfast_articulation_1.0_130427_1.pdf. Last accessed 6 Aug 2017

  • Swofford H (2015) Use of the term “identification” in latent print technical reports. Information paper. U.S. Army Criminal Investigation Laboratory, Defense Forensic Science Center, 3 Nov 2015

  • Swofford H (2017) Modification of latent print technical reports to include statistical calculations. Information paper. U.S. Army Criminal Investigation Laboratory, Defense Forensic Science Center, 9 Mar 2017

  • Swofford HJ, Koertner AJ, Zemp F, Ausdemore M, Liu A, Salyards MJ (2018) A method for the statistical interpretation of friction ridge skin impression evidence: method development and validation. Forensic Sci Int 287:113–126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taroni F, Bozza S, Aitken CGG (2005) Decision analysis in forensic science. J Forensic Sci 50:894–905

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taroni F, Bozza S, Biedermann A, Garbolino G, Aitken CGG (2010) Data analysis in forensic science: a Bayesian decision perspective. Statistics in practice. Wiley, Chichester

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson WC, Black J, Jain A, Kadane J (2017) Latent fingerprint examination, Forensic science assessments: a quality and gap analysis. American Association for the Advancement of Science, Washington

    Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann J, Morgenstern O (1944) Theory of games and economic behavior. Wiley, New York

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Willis S, McKenna L, McDermott S, O’Donell G, Barrett A, Rasmusson B, Nordgaard A, Berger C, Sjerps M, Lucena-Molina J, Zadora G, Aitken C, Lovelock T, Lunt L, Champod C, Biedermann A, Hicks T, Taroni F (2015) ENFSI guideline for evaluative reporting in forensic science, strengthening the evaluation of forensic results across Europe (STEOFRAE), Dublin

Download references

Acknowledgements

Alex Biedermann gratefully acknowledges the support of the Swiss National Science Foundation through Grant No. BSSGI0_155809 and the University of Lausanne. Some of the writing of this paper was carried out during a visiting research stay of Alex Biedermann at New York University School of Law.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to A. Biedermann.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Biedermann, A., Bozza, S. & Taroni, F. Normative decision analysis in forensic science. Artif Intell Law 28, 7–25 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10506-018-9232-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10506-018-9232-2

Keywords

Navigation