Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Building Risk into the Mitigation/Adaptation Decisions simulated by Integrated Assessment Models

  • Published:
Environmental and Resource Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper proposes an operationally simple and easily generalizable methodology to incorporate climate change damage uncertainty into Integrated Assessment Models (IAMs). First uncertainty is transformed into a risk measure by extracting damage distribution means and variances from an ensemble of socio economic and climate change scenarios. Then a risk premium is computed under different degrees of risk aversion, quantifying what society would be willing to pay to insure against the uncertainty of the damages. Our estimates show that the premium for the risk is a potentially significant addition to the “standard average damage”, but highly sensitive to the attitudes toward risk. In the last research phase, the risk premium is incorporated into the climate change damage function of a widely used IAM which shows, consequently, a substantial increase in both mitigation and adaptation efforts, reflecting a more precautionary attitude by the social planner. Interestingly, adaptation is stimulated more than mitigation in the first half of this century, while the situation reverses afterwards.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1

Source: authors’ elaboration. There are two possible states of the world/temperature: T1 associated to low and T2 associated to high damages, with probability P1 and P2 respectively. Due to risk aversion the dis-utility function is convex in damages. The utility loss associated to the expected damage UL(E(D(T))) (corresponding to loosing E(D(T)) with certainty) is lower than the expected utility loss E(UL(D(T))). The Damage Certainty Equivalent CE(D(T)) is thus larger than the expected damage E(D(T)). The difference, is the risk premium

Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Uncertainty about objective probabilities does not prevent agents from forming subjective probabilities.

  2. In-depth review of IAMs’ limitations are beyond the scope of the paper, we point the interested reader to Stern (2013) and Pindyck (2013) as just two paramount examples in this vein.

  3. Exercises like EMF (https://emf.stanford.edu/), ISI-MIP (https://www.pik-potsdam.de/research/climate-impacts-and-vulnerabilities/research/rd2-cross-cutting-activities/isi-mip) and AgMIP (http://www.agmip.org/) well illustrate this approach.

  4. See Anderson et al. (2014) for a discussion and new approaches on sensitivity tests.

  5. http://www.witchmodel.org.

  6. The risk adjusted rate is given by r where r = rf + βπ, where rf is the risk free discount rate, β is the elasticity of net benefit of the investment with respect to a change in aggregate consumption and π is the systematic risk premium. A value of β > 1, that is what authors find in relation to mitigation policies, implies an increase in the discount rate to be applied.

  7. See Kousky et al. (2011) for a review of the different methodologies to measure risk premium to be included in the social cost of carbon.

  8. Applications of the theory to understand investments decisions in finance are commonplace. See for example, Levy (1994) and Blake (1996) as well as the excellent notes of Professor Norstad. http://www.norstad.org/finance/util.pdf. An application to environmental decision-making is Krupnick et al. (1993). Note that we are using the concept of expected utility to elicit the risk premium but we are not applying the expected utility framework in the full sense of the CCAPM model, which we regard as inappropriate for this kind of analysis.

  9. In practice all the links in the chain from temperature to damages may be multiplicative. Certainly the relationship between temperature and economic damages is, but if the others were not, the use of the log normal will be more of an approximation.

  10. The literature on risk aversion indicates that the coefficient of relative risk aversion may increase with the size of the income loss or gain (Arrow 1965; Holt and Laury 2002). In this respect an alternative utility function (the exponential function) may be more appropriate. This takes the form: \(U(x) = \frac{{ - \exp^{ - \gamma x} }}{\gamma }\). In this case the coefficient of relative risk aversion is given by γx. Studies show, however that for variations in x that are small relative to total x (which in our case is GDP) a constant relative risk aversion function is a reasonable approximation.

  11. The WITCH model outcomes are amply referenced in the Fifth Assessment Report of the IPCC (Clarke et al. 2014) and in many model inter-comparison exercises (Bosetti et al. 2015, Lessmann, et al. 2015, Tavoni et al 2014) placing WITCH among the established models in the integrated assessment community. For detailed information on the WITCH model we address the interest reader to: http://www.witchmodel.org/.

  12. The WITCH model thus, sharing this feature with a whole stock of IAMs, uses reduced form climate change damage functions. I.e. all the complexities of impact assessments are compacted in few parameters. This simplification is particularly useful for the present exercises. For more discussion on the pros and cons of reduced form damage functions see Bosello (2014).

  13. We also performed some sensitivity tests (see supplementary Appendix Table 4) showing, in general, a relatively small effect of forcing the two values to be the same. The sensitivity analysis also shows that for some values of ƞ in the WITCH utility function, the model cannot find an equilibrium. Specifically, assuming ƞ = 2, optimization for high-damage regions, such as Sub Saharan Africa, can be solved only if the pure rate of time preference ρ is adjusted downward. The economic intuition is the following: the case ƞ = 2 corresponds to a situation of high relative risk aversion and low willingness to substitute consumption inter-temporally. In this case future damages are high, as they incorporate a large premium for the risk, and representative agents in the model would have a stronger preference to consume everything today. Thus, from the Ramsey equation, an increase in ƞ reduces the growth rate of consumption, and, in our simulations, the reduction is “too much” to find a feasible intertemporal optimum. The resulting lower sensitivity of consumption growth to the gap between the interest rate and the pure rate of time preference can be compensated by reducing the pure rate of time preference ρ. Gollier (2002) shows how uncertainty in future consumption modifies the Ramsey equation in a similar way. The pure rate of time preference would be lower in order to induce precautionary savings. In the context of the debate on climate change discounting, Gollier (2008) and Dasgupta (2008) have also suggested a parameter combination of ƞ = 2 and ρ = 0.

  14. The quantitative characterization on the evolution of main social economic variables in the scenario (namely GDP and population) have been extracted from: https://secure.iiasa.ac.at/web-apps/ene/SspDb/dsd?Action = htmlpage&page = about.

  15. This computation is scarcely meaningful in a non-cooperative set up as almost all of the climate policy relies upon adaptation.

References

  • Agrawala S, Bosello F, Carraro C, De Cian E, Lanzi E, De Bruin K, Dellink R (2011) “PLAN or REACT? Analisys of adaptation costs and benefits Using Integrated Assessment Models. Clim Change Econ 2(3):1–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson B, Borgonovo E, Galeotti M, Roson R (2014) Uncertainty in integrated assessment modelling: can global sensitivity analysis be of help. Risk Anal 34:271–293

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ (1965) Aspects in the theory of risk bearing. Academic Bookstores, Helsinki

    Google Scholar 

  • Aven T (2010) On the need for restricting the probabilistic analysis in risk assessments to variability. Risk Anal 30(3):354–360

    Google Scholar 

  • Aven T, Renn O (2015) An evaluation of the treatment of risk and uncertainties in the IPCC reports on climate change. Risk Anal 35(4):701–712

    Google Scholar 

  • Blake D (1996) Efficiency, risk aversion and portfolio insurance: an analysis of financial asset portfolios held by investors in the United Kingdom. Econ J 106:1175–1192

    Google Scholar 

  • Bliss RR, Panigirtzoglou N (2004) Option implied risk aversion parameters. J Financ, LIX, pp 407–444

    Google Scholar 

  • Bosello F (2014) The role of economic modelling for climate change mitigation and adaptation strategies. In: Markandya A, Galarraga I, Sainz de Murieta E (eds) Routledge handbook of the economics of climate change adaptation. Routledge, Oxon and New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bosello F, Carraro C, De Cian E (2010) Climate policy and the optimal balance between mitigation, adaptation and unavoided damage. Clim Change Econ 1(2):71–92

    Google Scholar 

  • Bosello F, Carraro C, De Cian E (2013) Can adaptation help mitigation? an integrated approach to post-2012 climate policy. Environ Dev Econ 18:270–290

    Google Scholar 

  • Bosello F, De Cian E (2014) Documentation on the development of damage functions and adaptation module in the WITCH model. http://www.witchmodel.org/pag/publications.html

  • Bosetti V, Carraro C, Galeotti M, Massetti E, Tavoni M (2006) WITCH: A World Induced Technical Change Hybrid Model. Energ J Special Issue. Hybrid modeling of energy-environment policies: reconciling bottom-up and top-down, pp 13–38

  • Bosetti V, Marangoni G, Borgonovo E, Diaz Anadon L, Barron R, McJeon H, Politis S, Friley P (2015) Sensitivity to energy technology costs: a multi-model comparison analysis. Energ Policy. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2014.12.012

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cai Y, Judd KL, Lontzek TS (2013) The social cost of stochastic and irreversible climate change. NBER 18704

  • Dasgupta P (2008) Discounting Climate Change. J Risk Uncertainty 37:141–169

    Google Scholar 

  • Dietz S, Gollier C and Kessler L (2015) The Climate Beta. Centre for Climate Change Economics and Policy Working Paper No. 215

  • Drouet L, Bosetti V, Tavoni M (2015) Selection of climate policies under the uncertainties in the Fifth Assessment Report of the IPCC. Nature Climate Change 5:937–940

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellsberg D (1961) Risk, ambiguity and the savage axioms. Quart. J. of Ec. 75(4):643–669

    Google Scholar 

  • Felgenhauer T, de Bruin KC (2009) Optimal paths of climate change mitigation and adaptation under certainty and uncertainty. Int J Global Warming 1:66–88

    Google Scholar 

  • Garrick BJ (2010) Interval analysis versus probabilistic analysis. Risk Anal 30(3):369–370

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa I, Postlewaite AW, Schmeidler D (2008) Probability and uncertainty in economic modeling. J Econ Perspect 22(3):173–188

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa I, Postlewaite A, Schmeidler D (2009) Is it always rational to satisfy Savage’s axioms? Econ Philos 25(3):285–296

    Google Scholar 

  • Gjerde J, Grepperud S, Kverndokk S (1999) Optimal climate policy under the possibility of a catastrophe. Res En Ec 21(3–4):289–317

    Google Scholar 

  • Gollier C (2002) Time horizon and the discount rate. J Econ Theory 107:463–473

    Google Scholar 

  • Gollier C (2008) Discounting with fat-tailed economic growth. J Risk Uncertainty 37:171–186

    Google Scholar 

  • Green PE, Krieger AM, Wind Y (2001) Thirty years of conjoint analysis: reflections and prospects. Interfaces 200131(3 Supplement):S56–S73

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall JW, Lempert RJ, Keller K, Hackbarth A, Mijere C, Mcinerney DJ (2012) Robust climate policies under uncertainty : a comparison of robust decision making and info-gap methods. Risk Anal 32(10):1657–1672

    Google Scholar 

  • Halsnæs K, Shukla P, Ahuja D, Akumu G, Beale R, Edmonds J, Gollier C, Grübler A, Ha Duong M, Markandya A, McFarland A, Nikitina Sugiyama ET, Villavicencio A, Zou J (2007) Framing issues. In: Metz B, Davidson OR, Bosch PR, Dave R, Meyer LA (eds) Climate Change 2007: Mitigation. Contribution of Working Group III to the Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Holt CA, Laury SK (2002) Risk Aversion and Incentive Effects. Am Econ Rev 92(5):1644–1655

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D (2011) Thinking fast and slow. Penguin Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan S, Garrick BJ (1981) On the quantitative definition of risk. Risk Anal 1(1):11–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplow L (2005) The Value of a statistical life and the coefficient of relative risk aversion. J Risk Uncertainty 31(1):23–34

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller K, Bolker BM, Bradford DF (2004) Uncertain climate thresholds and optimal economic growth. J Environ Econ Manag 48:723–741

    Google Scholar 

  • Klibanoff P, Marinacci M, Mukerji S (2005) A smooth model of decision making under ambiguity. Econometrica 73(6):1849–1892

    Google Scholar 

  • Klibanoff P, Marinacci M, Mukerji S (2009) Recursive smooth ambiguity preferences. J Econ Theory 144(3):930–976

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight FH (1921) Risk, uncertainty, and profit. Hart, Schaffner & Marx; Houghton Mifflin Company, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Kousky C, Kopp RE, Cooke RM (2011) Risk premia and the social cost of carbon: a review. Econ Open-Access Open-Assess E-J 5(2011-21):1

    Google Scholar 

  • Krupnick AJ, Markandya A, Nickell E (1993) The external costs of nuclear power: ex ante damages and lay risks. Am J Agr Econ 75:1273–1279

    Google Scholar 

  • Kunreuther H, Gupta S, Bosetti V, Cooke R, Dutt V, Ha-Duong M, Held H, Llanes-Regueiro J, Patt A, Shittu E, Weber E (2014) Integrated risk and uncertainty assessment of climate change response policies. In: Edenhofer O, Pichs-Madruga R, Sokona Y, Farahani E, Kadner S, Seyboth K, Adler A, Baum I, Brunner S, Eickemeier P, Kriemann B, Savolainen J, Schlömer S, von Stechow C, Zwickel T, Minx JC (eds) Climate Change 2014: Mitigation of Climate Change. Contribution of Working Group III to the Fifth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Layard R, Mayraz G, Nickell S (2008) The marginal utility of income. J Public Econ 8–9(92):1846–1857

    Google Scholar 

  • Lemoine DM, Traeger C (2012) Tipping points and ambiguity in the economics of climate change. NBER 18230

  • Lessmann K, Kornek U, Bosetti V, Dellink R, Emmerling J, Eyckmans J, Nagashima M, Weikard H-P, Yang Z (2015) The stability and effectiveness of climate coalitions: a comparative analysis of multiple integrated assessment models. Environ Resource Econ 1:1. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10640-015-9886-0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy H (1994) Absolute and relative risk aversion: an experimental study. J Risk Uncertainty 8:289–307

    Google Scholar 

  • Lucas RE (1978) Asset prices in an exchange economy. Econometrica 46:1429–1445

    Google Scholar 

  • Millner A, Dietz S, Heal G (2013) Scientific Ambiguity and Climate Policy. Environ Resource Econ 55:21–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Nordhaus WD (2008) A Question of balance: weighing the options on global warming policies. Yale University Press, Yale

    Google Scholar 

  • North WD (2010) Probability theory and consistent reasoning. Risk Anal 30(3):377–380

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill BC, Carter TR, Ebi KL, Edmonds J, Hallegatte S, Kemp-Benedict E, Kriegler E, Mearns L, Moss R, Riahi K, van Ruijven B, van Vuuren D (2012). Meeting Report of the Workshop on The Nature and Use of New Socioeconomic Pathways for Climate Change Research, Boulder, CO, November 2–4, 2011. http://www.isp.ucar.edu/socio-economic-pathways

  • Pindyck R (2013) Climate change policy: what do the models tell us? J Econlit 51(3):860–872

    Google Scholar 

  • Rabl A, Spadaro JV (1999) Environmental damages and costs: an analysis of uncertainties. Environ Int 25(1):29–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Shiller R (2000) Irrational exuberance. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern N (2013) The structure of economic modeling of the potential impacts of climate change: grafting gross underestimation of risk onto already narrow science models. J Econ Lit 51(3):838–859

    Google Scholar 

  • Tavoni M, Kriegler E, Riahi K, van Vuuren DP, Aboumahboub T, Bowen A, Calvin K, Campiglio E, Kober T, Jewell J, Luderer G, Marangoni G, McCollum D, van Sluisveld M, Zimmer A, van der Zwaan B (2014) Post-2020 climate agreements in the major economies assessed in the light of global models. Nat Clim Change. https://doi.org/10.1038/nclimate2475

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor K, Stouffer R, Meehl G (2012) An overview of CMIP5 and the experiment design. Bull Am Meteor Soc 93:485–498

    Google Scholar 

  • Thaler RH, Sunstein CR (2008) Nudge: improving decisions about health, wealth and happiness. Yale University Press, New Haven

    Google Scholar 

  • Urban NM, Keller K (2010) Probabilistic hindcasts and projections of the coupled climate, carbon cycle and Atlantic meridional overturning circulation system: a Bayesian fusion of century-scale observations with a simple model. Tellus A 62(5):737–750

    Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann J, Morgenstern O (1944) Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Weitzman M (2009a) Additive damages, fat-tailed climate dynamics, and uncertain discounting. economics: the open-access. Open-Assess E-J 3:2009–2039

    Google Scholar 

  • Weitzman M (2009b) On modeling and interpreting the economics of catastrophic climate change. Rev Econ Stat 91:1–19

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Part of the research leading to the completion of this paper has been funded by the European Community’s Seventh Framework Program under Grant Agreement No. 308337 (BASE) and No 298436 (DYNAMIC).J.M.P.M. was funded by a Basque Government post-doctoral fellowship.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Francesco Bosello.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

We ran the SSP2 with and without adjustment in the ηcoefficient in the model and results show that the adjustment to set it equal to the coefficient of risk aversion does not have a big impact when the non–cooperative solution is implemented (Table 4). The same applies when we make small changes to the pure rate of time preference (ρ) (See Tables 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, Fig. 8).

Table 4 Change in total adaptation expenditure and CO2 emissions in three time slices relative to the case with no risk premium. Regional action (non-cooperative Nash game), scenarios SSP2
Table 5 WITCH model regions
Table 6 Data on damage distribution as a function of temperature change
Table 7 Risk-premium adjusted damages for ƞ = 1
Table 8 Risk-premium adjusted damages for ƞ = 1.5
Table 9 Risk-premium adjusted damages for ƞ = 2
Fig. 8
figure 8

Akaike Information Criteria (AIC) of the fitting of damages with different distribution (the lower the better)

The sensitivity analysis also shows that for some values of ƞ in the WITCH utility function, the model cannot find an equilibrium. Specifically, assuming ƞ = 2, optimization for high-damage regions, such as Sub Saharan Africa, can be solved only if the pure rate of time preference ρ is adjusted downward. The economic intuition is the following: the case ƞ = 2 corresponds to a situation of high relative risk aversion and low willingness to substitute consumption inter-temporally. In this case future damages are high, as they incorporate a large premium for the risk, and representative agents in the model would have a stronger preference to consume everything today. Thus, from the Ramsey equation, an increase in ƞ reduces the growth rate of consumption, and, in our simulations, the reduction is “too much” to find a feasible intertemporal optimum. The resulting lower sensitivity of consumption growth to the gap between the interest rate and the pure rate of time preference can be compensated by reducing the pure rate of time preference ρ. Gollier (2002) shows how uncertainty in future consumption modifies the Ramsey equation in a similar way. The pure rate of time preference would be lower in order to induce precautionary savings. In the context of the debate on climate change discounting, Gollier (2008) and Dasgupta (2008) have also suggested a parameter combination of ƞ = 2 and ρ = 0.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Markandya, A., De Cian, E., Drouet, L. et al. Building Risk into the Mitigation/Adaptation Decisions simulated by Integrated Assessment Models. Environ Resource Econ 74, 1687–1721 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10640-019-00384-1

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10640-019-00384-1

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation