Skip to main content
Log in

Enlanguaged experience. Pragmatist contributions to the continuity between experience and language

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I present the idea of “enlanguaged experience” as a radicalization of the Pragmatists’ approach to the continuity between language and experience in the human world as a concept that can provide a significant contribution to the current debate within Enactivism. The first part of the paper explores some new conceptual tools recently developed by enactivist scholarship, namely linguistic bodies, enlanguaged affordances, and languaging. In the second part, the notion of enlanguaged experience is introduced as involving two main interrelated ideas. The first is the idea that human experience is contingently, yet irreversibly, embedded from each person’s birth within contexts made up of linguistic practices that contribute to continuously redefining what happens. Consequently, the development of individuals’ motor, perceptual, affective, selective, and cognitive capacities does not take place in a silent vacuum, but in a context of linguistic practices that are already there: such practices already operate in, and are shared by, the human groups in which individuals begin their experiences. The second key idea is that enlanguaged experience implies the claim that humans primarily meet language as part of their experience of the world, rather than as an independent system of words and grammar. In the third part of the paper, I argue that the conception of human experience as enlanguaged can fruitfully contribute to the enactivist debate, particularly with reference to three main points: firstly, the idea of a circular continuity, which is to say the claim that the advent of language in human life caused a re-configuration of previously existing forms of sensibility both ontogenetically and phylogenetically; secondly, an ecological view of language, according to which humans find themselves embedded in already operating linguistic practices and habits that are a constitutive part of their naturally social world; and, thirdly, a richer view of language “in the wild”, capable of retrieving the qualitative, affective, or aesthetic components of human enlanguaged experience.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This statement does not deny that there is an ambiguity in James’ treatment of language because of his criticism of language as favoring an atomistic conception of thought as primarily composed of discrete units, insofar as language itself is manly conceived of as consisting in an association of names. Sometimes this critical approach coexists in the same text with a more dynamic view of language and meanings, as is the case in the famous chapter on the stream of thought in the Principles (James 1981, Ch. IX). Moreover, James seems to adopt a dichotomous understanding of the relation between concepts and experience (see the treatment of the deaf-mute case in James 1983) and consistently supports the claim of the priority of experience over thought (cf. James 1976). I have dealt with this issue extensively in Author.

  2. See Bernstein 2020 for a picture of Dewey’s “pragmatic naturalism”.

  3. For limitations in terms of space and expertise, here I will not discuss Charles Peirce’s insights on the subject and how they might contribute to the current debate in Enactivism. For an in-depth treatment of semiotics and the application of cognitive science to the study of signs, mind, and language see Paolucci 2021, whose research approach combines both Peirce’s and Eco’s legacy.

  4. For an in-depth analysis of the meanings of affordance and its functions, see Manuel Heras-Escribano 2019.

  5. Although for the purposes of this paper, I am dealing with the various scholarly approaches to “languaging” as essentially convergent, they actually form a complex constellation of thought, insofar as they support at least two main views. One group of scholars restricts “languaging” to bio-logic (Raimondi 2019), linguistic techniques (Bottineau 2017) and practices (Cowley 2011) providing a new reconceptualization of language. Other scholars reject “language” by stressing that practices (not just communication) presuppose the logic of languaging, thereby adopting a quasi-transcendental approach. For example, radical ecolinguists, inspired by Becker's (1988) anthropology, challenge linguistics by drawing on Heidegger, Wittgenstein, and a reading of Maturana's work. I am grateful to one of the anonymous reviewer for pointing out this important caveat.

  6. In writing this paper, I wondered whether it might be appropriate to characterize the Pragmatists’ view of experience as ‘externalist’. It is, of course, if by ‘externalist’ one means ‘non-internalist’. However, it is not an externalist view in standard behaviorist terms, namely a view exclusively focused on directly observable actions and behavior. For Dewey and Mead, even brain processes and memories, i.e. so-called internal events, are part of experience insofar as they flow into organic-environmental interactions. The point is that they should not be thought of as the main, and possibly causal, features of experience, because – as Dewey already noted in his criticism of brain-centrism – it is not a brain that thinks, perceives, and acts, but an organism interacting with specific situations and contexts (cf. Boyles & Garrison 2017).

  7. From what has been argued so far, it should be evident that the claim that human experience is enlanguaged is developed within a naturalistic framework, implying that experience contingently derives from the reorganization of previously existing organic and environmental resources. Coherently with the pragmatist legacy, this view remains distant from quasi-transcendentalist approaches to language as the enabling condition of human experience, such as those adopted by Apel, McDowell, and Brandom (see Author, Ch. 5).

  8. For a more detailed account of Frank Lorimer’s picture of language, its relation to reason, and their common roots in living processes, see Dreon forthcoming.

  9. George Herbert Mead made at least another important contribution to the study of the continuity between affective experience and linguistic interactions, by providing some interesting insights into the emergence of linguistic conversations out of emotion-based interactions. In Mead’s view, emotions serve as a means to mutually regulate social conduct while still maintaining a crucial role in verbal communication (see Dreon 2019). See Guido Baggio’s paper in the current issue of the journal for a comprehensive discussion of Mead’s theory of gestures as an attempt to overcome the dichotomic view of lower and higher level cognition (Baggio 2023).

References

  • Becker, A. L. (1988). Language in Particular: A Lecture. In D. Tannen (Ed.), Linguistic in Context: Connecting Observation and Understanding (pp. 17–35). Ablex.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baggio, G. (2023), Gesture, Meaning and Intentionality. From Radical to Pragmatist Enactive Theory of Language. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-023-09936-9

  • Bernstein, R. J. (2020). Pragmatic Naturalism. John Dewey’s Living Legacy, AmazonBooks. Originally printed as Bernstein, R.J. (2019). Pragmatic Naturalism. John Dewey’s Living Legacy. Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal, 40(2), 527–594.

  • Black, M. (1962). Dewey’s Philosophy of Language. The Journal of Philosophy, 59(19), 505–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bottineau, D. (2017). Du Languaging Au Sens Linguistic. Intellectica, 1(68), 19–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bottineau, D., & Grégoire, M. (2017). Le langage humain, les langues et la parole du point de vue du languaging et de l’énaction. Intellectica, 1(68), 7–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bottineau, D. (2008). Language and Enaction. Stewart, J., Gapenne, O. & Di Paolo, E. (Eds.) Enaction: towards a new paradigm for cognitive science, MIT, 1–67.

  • Boyles, D., & Garrison, J. (2017). The mind is not the Brain: John Dewey, Neuroscience, and Avoiding the Mereological Fallacy. Dewey Studies, 1(1), 111–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calcaterra, R. M. (2019). Contingency and normativity. The challenges of Richard Rorty. Brill Rodopi.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing Without Representing? Synthese, 101, 401–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cometti, J.- P. (unpublished manuscript) (n.d.). Le naturalism pragmatiste. Experience, langage et action sociale

  • Cowley, S. J. (2011). Taking a language stance. Ecological Psychology, 23(3), 185–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cowley, S. J. (2019). The Return of Languaging: Toward a New Ecolinguistics. Chinese Semiotic Studies, 15(4), 483–512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cuffari, E. C., Di Paolo, E., & De Jaegher, H. (2015). From Participatory Sense-making to Language: There and back again. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 14(4), 1089–1125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1991). Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, The Later Works, Volume12. Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1981). Experience and Nature. The Later Works, Volume 1. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press.

  • Dewey, J. (1989). Art as Experience. The Later Works, Volume 10. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press.

  • Di Paolo, E. A., De Jaegher, H., & Cuffari, E. C. (2018). Linguistic Bodies. The Continuity between Life and Language. MIT.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dissanayake, E. (2001). Aesthetic Incunabula. Philosophy and Literature, 25(2), 335–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreon, R. (2007). Il sentire e la parola. Linguaggio e sensibilità tra filosofie ed estetiche del novecento. Milan: Mimesis.

  • Dreon, R. (2019). Gesti emotivi e gesti verbali. L’eredità di George Herbert Mead sulla genesi del linguaggio umano. Sistemi intelligenti, 1, 115–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreon, R. (2020). James on the Stream of Language: with some Remarks on his Influence on Wittgenstein. Cognitio, 21(1), 68–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreon, R. (2022). Human Landscapes. Contributions to a Pragmatist Anthropology. New York: Suny Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreon, R. (forthcoming). Language, and Life. Frank Lorimer’s Critical Development of Dewey’s Approach. Bella, M., Ferrucci, F., Maddalena, G., Santarelli, M. (Eds.), Gestures. New Meanings for an Old Word, De Gruyter.

  • Dreyfus, H. (2007). Overcoming the Myth of the Mental: How Philosophers Can Profit from Phenomenology of Everyday Expertise. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 79(2), 47–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Faerna, A. M. (2018). In Search of the Lost Body: On Pragmatism, Experience, and Language. Pragmatism Today, 9(2), 107–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gavin, W. J. (1992). William James and the Reinstatement of the Vague. Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heras-Escribano, M. (2019). The Philosophy of Affordances. Palgrave.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hildebrand, D. (2014). Language or Experience. Charting Pragmatism’s Course for the 21st Century (Ed.). European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, VI/2.

  • Husserl, E. (1973). Experience and Judgement. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds Without Content. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackman, H. (2017). William James on Conceptions and Private Language. Belgrade Philosophical Annual, 30, 175–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1976). Essays in Radical Empiricism. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1981). The Principles of Psychology. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1983). Thought Before Language: A Deaf-mute’s Recollection. In Essays in Psychologyy. Cambridge, MA, and London: Harvard University Press, 1983, p. 278-291.

  • Kiverstein, J., & Rietveld, E. (2018). Representation Hungry Cognition Reconceived: An Ecological-Enactive Proposal. Adaptive Behaviour, 26(4), 147–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiverstein, J., & Rietveld, E. (2021). Scaling-up Skilled Intentionality to Linguistic Thought. Synthese, 198(Suppl. 1), 175–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland, K. N., Odling-Smee, J. O., & Feldman, M.-W. (2000). Niche Construction, Biological Evolution, and Cultural Change. Behavioural and Brain-Sciences, 23, 131–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lorimer, F. (1929). The Growth of Reason. A Study of the Role of Verbal Activity in the Growth of the Structure of the Human Mind. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Love, N. (2017). On Languaging and Languages. Language Sciences, 61, 113–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J. (2009). The Arts and the Definition of the Human. Toward a Philosophical Anthropology. Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J. (2016). Toward a Metaphysic of Culture. Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J. (2017). Three Paradoxes of Personhood. The Venetian Lectures. Mimesis International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mead, G. H. (1922). ABbehavioristic Account of the Significant Symbol. Journal of Philosophy, 19, 157–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mead, G. H. (2011). Essays in Social Psycology. Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mithen, S., & Parsons, L. (2008). The Brain as a Cultural Artefact. Cambridge Archeological Journal, 18(3), 415–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paolucci, C. (2021). Cognitive Semiotics: Integrating Signs. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pearce, T. (2020). Pragmatism’s Evolution. Organism and Environment in American Philosophy. The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raimondi, V. (2019). The Bio-logic of Languaging and its Epistemological Background, Language Sciences, 71, 19–26.

  • Rietveld, E., & Kiverstein, J. (2014). The Rich Landscape of Affordances. Ecological Psychology, 26(4), 325–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1982). Consequences of Pragmatism. Essays: 1972–1980. University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (2007). In the Space of Reasons. Sharp, K. & Brandom, R. Eds. Havard University Press.

  • Sinha, C. (2015). Language and Other Artifacts: Socio-cultural Dynamics of Niche Construction. Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sinha, C. (2009). Language as a Biocultural Niche and Social Institution. Evans, V., Pourcel, S. (Eds.). New Directions in Cognitive Linguistics. John Benjamins, 289–309.

  • Steffensen, S.V., Cowley, S. J. (2021). Thinking on Behalf of the World: Radical Embodied Ecolinguistic. X. Wen, J. R. Taylor (Eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Cognitive Linguistics, London, Routledge, 723–736.

  • Steiner, P. (2019). Désaturer l’esprit. Usages du pragmatism. Questions théoriques.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voparil, C. (2022). Richard Rorty and the Classical Pragmatists. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

I received financial support from my University (Ca’ Foscari University, Venice) and from my Department (Department of Philosophy and Cultural Heritage) to publish Open Access.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

I confirm the sole responsibility for conception and manuscript preparation.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roberta Dreon.

Ethics declarations

Ethical approval

The manuscript has not be submitted to other journals for simultaneous consideration.

The submitted work is original and have not been published elsewhere in any form or language (partially or in full).

No data, text, or theories by others has been presented as if they were my own (‘plagiarism’). Proper acknowledgements to other works has be given, quotation marks are used for verbatim copying of material, and permissions secured for material that is copyrighted.

Informed consent

Not applicable.

Statement regarding research involving human participants and/or animals

Not applicable.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dreon, R. Enlanguaged experience. Pragmatist contributions to the continuity between experience and language. Phenom Cogn Sci (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-023-09950-x

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-023-09950-x

Keywords

Navigation