Skip to main content
Log in

Framing cognition: Dewey’s potential contributions to some enactivist issues

  • S.I.: Radical Views on Cognition
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is well known that John Dewey was very far from embracing the traditional idea of cognition as something happening inside one’s own mind and consisting in a pictorial representation of the alleged purely external reality out there. His position was largely convergent with enactivist accounts of cognition as something based in life and consisting in human actions within a natural environment. The paper considers Dewey’s conception of cognition by focusing on its potential contributions to the current debate with enactivism. It claims that Dewey’s anti-substantial, continuistic, and emergentistic conception of the mind as a typically human conduct pulls the rug out of the idea of cognition as representation, as well as pushes the current discussion towards a serious reconsideration of representationalist assumptions about conceptuality and language. The paper emphasises that Dewey—differently from enactivists—frames the role of cognition within experience: he argues that cognition concerns those intermediate phases of our experiences of the world which are characterised by an indeterminate or troubled situation, because he claims that human beings’ interactions with their own environment are qualitatively richer and broader than cognition, including as they do many different and intertwined modes of experience. Finally, the author suggests that a coherent development of Dewey’s lines of thought should avoid rigid distinctions and hierarchies between lower and higher degrees of cognition in humans, which are still maintained in certain forms of radical enactivism. Differently, we should consider the impact of the cultural and broadly linguistic configuration of the human–environment even on perception, motor action, and affective sensibility.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The 1991 volume (Varela et al. 1991) makes various references (in the notes, the bibliography, and part of the text itself) to authors from the heterogeneous tradition of neo-pragmatism, such as Hilary Putnam, Richard Rorty, Richard Bernstein and Joseph Margolis, who nonetheless are not identified as pragmatists. As already noted, the text makes not reference to the authors of classical American pragmatism, including William James. On the differences in the use of the adjective “pragmatic” and “pragmatist” in enactivist literature, see the interesting article by Steiner (2017).

  2. See, among other works, Johnson (2010) and Menary (2015). On the mutual engagement between pragmatism and the cognitivist sciences, see too the volumes edited by Solymosi and Shook (2014) and by Madzia and Jung (2016). The topic has also been the focus of an issue of the journal Pragmatism Today (Madzia and Santarelli [Eds.] 2017).

  3. Some serious work engaging with the cognitive sciences on the basis of classical pragmatism has been carried out by Pierre Steiner in recent years. See Steiner (2008, 2014, 2017).

  4. By contrast, here I will not address the thorny issue of the ways in which mental states are correlated with neural processes, which is to say of the way in which semantic contents might be embedded within a syntactic system (on this see Steiner 2014).

  5. I am grateful to Pierre Steiner, who at a seminar he gave in Venice in December 2018 brought to my attention the fact that in current cognitive sciences there are also non-mentalistic representationalist positions, which support an eliminativist approach to the mental and consider contentful states of the brain as having nothing whatsoever to do with representative functions, in the metaphorical sense of the term—insfoar as these states do not stay for or mirror extracranial states of things.

  6. This kind of approach takes as its starting point not a disembodied awareness dealing with a reality that exists out there, even prior to any human intervention, but rather an organism which finds itself in an environment that precedes its individual existence, and of which it is at the same time an integral part. The organism, in turn, modifies this environment and dynamically reconfigures it from within. An approach of this sort allows Deweyan pragmatism to avoid the fruitless opposition between naive realism and idealism. In other words, this perspective makes it possible to avoid the opposition between the assumption of a reality that is already entirely predetermined, and which the knower must strive to faithfully mirror, and the assumption that reality is merely a subjective construct. See Hildebrand (2003). Somewhat similar claims are made in the chapter on “Cartesian Anxiety” in the volume by Varela et al. (1991, p. 133 ff.). Significantly, this formula was first used by Richard Bernstein, who was one of the few pragmatists at a time when this tradition was almost entirely ignored in the United States.

  7. For a more in-depth examination of Dewey's notion of situation, see Steiner (2008, § 3) and Gallagher (2017, p. 54 ff.).

  8. Mead, who had worked closely with Dewey on these issues, also stressed the centrality of inhibition for understanding the specificity of intelligent human behaviour compared to other forms of animal intelligence. See esp. the essays What Social Objects Must Psychology Presuppose? Emotion and Instinct, and The Child and His Environment in Mead (2011).

  9. On this point see the very clear view of Arteaga: “Obviously, the enactive concept of cognition implies an extension of the common meaning of this term. Cognition in this context is not reduced to the production, development or achievement of an explanation or a skill—in reference respectively to the concept of ‘knowing that’ and ‘knowing how’—about something else: respectively an object or state of affairs or a task. Cognition is not reduced here to a mere question of problem-solving. To solve a concrete problem or to develop the necessary skills to do it configure specific aspects of cognition but define neither exhaustively nor fundamentally this term. The enactive concept of cognition refers to the fundamental activities of being alive, of finding ways to maintain life, to preserve the viability of the living unit’s active-being-in-the-world in and with the worlds that emerge out of life’s own processes, which simultaneously enable living units to achieve and maintain their own selfness” (Arteaga 2017, p. 23).

  10. On this issue see Dreon (2018).

  11. See the 1868 essays Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man and Some Consequences of Four Incapacities (Peirce 1992a, b). The question of whether it is possible to draw a clear-cut distinction between perception and higher cognitive processes is also addressed by Mead in an essay entitled Concerning Animal Perception (in Mead 2011), which ultimately gives a negative answer.

  12. As other scholars have noted, a crucial work on this issue is the essay on the reflex arc that Dewey wrote as early as 1896 (Dewey 1972).

  13. Pierre Steiner defines this approach to the mind as “adverbialist” in Steiner (2017).

  14. See the 1908 essay The Logical Character of Ideas, reprinted in Essays in Experimental Logic in 1916 (Dewey 2004).

  15. Here a long series of references could be provided, starting from the fathers of enactivism: Varela et al. (1991), Hutto and Myin (2013), Colombetti (2014) and Gallagher (2017)—to quote but a few.

  16. See esp. the 1917 essay The Need for Social Psychology (Dewey 1980b), from which a very close collaboration with Mead may be inferred.

  17. From this perspective, we find a convergence with the emphasis placed by enactivists (both in Varela et al. 1991, p. 185 ff.; Gallagher 2017, p. 168) on the notion of exaptation and of the reuse of previous resources for new ends of contemporary evolutionist thought. Obviously, Stephen Gould’s work on these issues was unknown to Dewey and the pragmatists, but the reading of Darwin formulated by Chauncey Wright, a former member of the famous Metaphysical Club, already went in this direction. See Parravicini (2012).

  18. This is closely reminiscent of the enactivist emphasis on emergent properties. See Varela et al. (1991, p. 88).

  19. As is known, this label was used to describe James’ and Dewey’s psychological theories. We owe to James Rowland Angell, also a member of the Chicago School, the definition of the term: “The functional psychologist then in his modern attire is interested not alone in the operations of mental process considered merely of and by and for itself, but also and more vigorously in mental activity as part of a larger stream of biological forces which are daily and hourly at work before our eyes and which are constitutive of the most important and most absorbing part of our world. The psychologist of this stripe is wont to take his cue from the basal conception of the evolutionary movement, i.e., that for the most part organic structures and functions possess their present characteristics by virtue of the efficiency with which they fit into the extent conditions of life broadly designated the environment. With this conception in mind he [p. 69] proceeds to attempt some understanding of the manner in which the psychical contributes to the furtherance of the sum total of organic activities, not alone the psychical in its entirety, but especially the psychical in its particularities—mind as judging, mind as feeling, etc.” (Angell 1907, pp. 68–69). Therefore, I believe that the characterisation of Dewey’s philosophy of mind in functionalist terms is not subject to Gallagher’s criticism of Andy Clark’s extended mind approach, which would ultimately weaken the specificity of the human body with respect to the development of cognition (Gallagher 2017, p. 36).

  20. From this perspective, the transition from “suggestions” to “affordances”—the relevance of which for enactivism is well-known—as invitations to act in a certain way does not seem far-off.

  21. Varela, Thompson and Rosch speak of the selection of salient environmental features by organisms as a form of interpretation (Varela et al. 1991, p. 156).

  22. In my view, this is the aspect of cultural naturalism closest to the enactivist concepts of autopoiesis and autonomy, as they regard the organism-environment system, rather than only the individual organisms involved. See Varela et al. (1991, p. 103 and p. 156) and Colombetti (2014, p. 15–19).

  23. See William James’s emphasis—already in Principles of Psychology—on the plasticity of the nervous system, understood not as a machine with pre-installed programmes that functions autonomously, but as a sound board that configures itself through the reverberation of environmental events (see esp. the chapter on habits and the one on emotions).

  24. In this respect, Dewey and Mead’s pragmatism would appear to foreshadow Tomasello’s conclusions regarding the social dimension of the evolution of human culture, as well as his thesis that human cognitive evolution is largely based not just on biological resources, but also on cultural resources (Tomasello 1999). On this point, see Dreon (2019a).

  25. Dewey’s claims against armchair philosophy did not prevent him, however, from drawing upon Hegel—as well as James. I believe that the influence of Hegelian thought is visible in the passage just quoted, if only in naturalised form (Rorty 1991), whereby the truth is the whole and not the isolated part, which instead coincides with the abstract truth in Hegel’s philosophy. In addition, it is important to recall the notion of Erfahrung, which in the Phenomenology of the Spirit plays a crucial role, to the detriment of the subjectivist idea of experience associated with the history of the term Erlebnis.

  26. This is also clear to many scholars from the enactivist camp and, more generally, to all theorists of the embodied, embedded, extended and enactive mind (Clark 2006; De Jaegher and Di Paolo 2007; Spurrett and Cowley 2010; Gallagher 2013; Krueger 2013; Fusaroli et al. 2014).

  27. It must be recalled, however, that non-representational explanations are possible even in the case of high-level cognitive processes, according to Daniel Hutto. See Hutto (2017) on the role of narrativity in autobiographical memory.

  28. The same doubt is also voiced by Steiner (2014, p. 46).

  29. This is shown not just by Dewey’s pedagogical interests but also by his personal experience, as we read in Dyehouse and Manke (2017).

  30. On Dewey's conception of language see Dreon (2014). On Mead’s view of language see Dreon (2019). When I was correcting the last draft of my text for publication in this journal issue, the promising book Linguistic Bodies. The Continuity Between Life and Language by Ezequiel Di Paolo, Elena Cuffari and Hanna De Jaegher was published. It will deserve great attention in the ongoing debate between enactivism and the pragmatist heritage.

  31. I believe that with regard to this point a convergence can be found with the notion of primordial affectivity developed by Colombetti (2014). On the topic of emotions and affective sensibility in classical pragmatism, see Dreon (2019b).

References

  • Angell, J. R. (1907). The province of functional psychology. The Psychological Review, XIV(2), 61–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arteaga, A. (2017). Embodied and situated aesthetics. An enactive approach to a cognitive notion of aesthetics. Artnodes, 20, 20–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Calcaterra, R. M. (2011). Varieties of synechism. Peirce and James on mind-world continuity. Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 25(4), 412–424.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2006). Language, embodiment, and the cognitive niche. Trends in Cognitive Neurosciences, 10(8), 370–374.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2014). The feeling body. Affective science meets the enactive mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cometti, J. P. (2015). Making the difference: John Dewey and the naturalization of aesthetics. Aisthesis, 8(1), 123–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. (2007). Participatory sense-making. An enactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6, 485–507.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1972). The reflex-arc concept in psychology. Volume 5 of the early works. Carbondale: Southern Illinois U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1978). Ethics. Volume 5 of the middle works. Carbondale: Southern Illinois U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1979). What are states of minds? Volume 7 of the middle works (pp. 31–43). Carbondale: Southern Illinois U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1980a). The need for a recovery of philosophy. Volume 10 of the middle works (pp. 3–48). Carbondale: Southern Illinois U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1980b). The need for social psychology. Volume 10 of the middle works (pp. 53–63). Carbondale: Southern Illinois U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1981). Experience and nature. Volume 1 of the later works. Carbondale: Southern Illinois U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1983). Human nature and conduct. Volume 14 of the middle works. Carbondale: Southern Illinois U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1985). Ethics. Volume 7 of the later works. Carbondale: Southern Illinois U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1988). Experience, knowledge, and value. A rejoinder. Volume 14 of the later works (pp. 3–90). Carbondale: Southern Illinois U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1989). Art as experience. Volume 10 of the later works. Carbondale: Southern Illinois U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1991). Logic: The theory of inquiry. Volume 12 of the later works. Carbondale: Southern Illinois U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (2004). Essays in experimental logic. New York: Dover Publication.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (2007). The influence of Darwin on philosophy. In L. Hickman (Ed.), The influence of Darwin on philosophy and other essays in contemporary thought (pp. 5–12). Carbondale: Southern Illinois U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dissanayake, E. (2011). Prelinguistic and preliterate substrates of poetic narrative. Poetics Today, 32(1), 55–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreon, R. (2007). Esperienza e linguaggio: Le risposte del “naturalismo culturale” di Dewey. In R. Dreon (Ed.), Il sentire e la parola (pp. 165–207). Mimesis: Milano-Udine.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreon, R. (2014). Dewey on language: Elements for a non-dualistic approach. European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy, VI(2), 109–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreon, R. (2018). Is there any room for immediate experience? Looking for an answer in Dewey (and Wittgenstein) via Peirce and James. Pragmatism Today, 9, 59–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreon, R. (2019a). Gesti emotivi e gesti verbali. L’eredità di George Herbert Mead sulla genesi del linguaggio umano. Sistemi intelligenti, I, 115–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreon, R. (2019b). A pragmatist view of emotions. Tracing its significance for the current debate. In L. Candiotto (Ed.), Emotions for knowledge (pp. 73–99). London: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. (2007). Why Heideggerian AI failed and how fixing it would require making it more Heideggerian. Philosophical Psychology, 20(2), 247–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus, H. (2013). The myth of the pervasiveness of the mental. The McDowell-Dreyfus debate. In J. K. Schear (Ed.), Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world (pp. 15–40). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dyehouse, J., & Manke, K. (2017). The philosopher as parent: John Dewey’s observations of his children’s language development and the development of his thinking about communication. Education and Culture, 33(1), 18–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Falk, D. (2004). Prelinguistic evolution in early hominins: Whence motherese? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27, 491–503.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fusaroli, R., Gangopadhyay, N., & Tylén, K. (2014). The dialogically extended mind: Language as skillful intersubjective engagement. Cognitive Systems Research, 29(30), 31–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2013). The socially extended mind. Cognitive Systems Research, 25(26), 4–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2017). Enactivist interventions. Rethinking the mind. Oxford: Oxford U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hildebrand, D. (2003). Beyond realism and antirealism: John Dewey and the neopragmatists. Nashville: Vanderbilt U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. (2017). Memory and narrativity. In S. Bernecker & K. Michaelian (Eds.), The routledge handbook of philosophy of memory (pp. 192–204). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism. Basic minds without content. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1981). Principles of psychology. In F. H. Burkhardt, F. Bowers, & I. K. Skrupskelis (Eds.), The works of William James. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. (2010). Cognitive science and Dewey’s theory of mind, thought, and language. In M. Cochran (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Dewey (pp. 123–144). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J. (2013). Ontogenesis of the socially extended mind. Cognitive Systems Research, 25(26), 40–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maddalena, G. (2015). The philosophy of gestures. Completing pragmatists’ incomplete revolution. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Madzia, R., & Jung, M. (Eds.). (2016). Pragmatism and embodied cognitive science. From bodily intersubjectivity to symbolic articulation. Berlin: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Madzia, R., & Santarelli, M. (Eds.). (2017). Pragmatism, cognitive science and the sociality of conduct. Pragmatism today (Vol. 8, No. 1). Europe: Central European Pragmatist Forum.

  • Margolis, J. (2002). Reinventing pragmatism. American philosophy at the end of the twentieth century. London: Cornell U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J. (2017). Three paradoxes of personhood. In R. Dreon (Ed.), The venetian lectures. Milano: Mimesis International.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (2013). The myth of the mind as detached. In J. K. Schear (Ed.), Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world. The McDowell-Dreyfus debate (pp. 41–58). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mead, G. H. (2011). Deegan, M. J. (Ed.), Essays in social psychology. London: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2015). Pragmatism and the pragmatic turn in cognitive science. In A. K. Engel, K. J. Friston, & D. Kragic (Eds.), The pragmatic turn. Toward action-oriented views in cognitive sciences (pp. 215–234). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2013). On overintellectualizing the intellect. In J. K. Schear (Ed.), Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world: The McDowell-Dreyfus debate (pp. 178–193). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parravicini, A. (2012). Il pensiero in evoluzione. Chauncy Wright tra darwinismo e pragmatismo. Pisa: ETS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1992a). Questions concerning certain faculties claimed for man (1868). In N. Houser & C. Kloesel (Eds.), The essential peirce (1867–1893) (Vol. 1, pp. 11–27). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1992b). Some consequences of four incapacities (1868). In N. Houser & C. Kloesel (Eds.), The essential peirce (1867–1893) (Vol. 1, pp. 28–55). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1991). Lumps and texts. In R. Rorty (Ed.), Objectivity, relativism, and truth (pp. 78–92). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schear, J. K. (Ed.). (2013). Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world. The McDowell-Dreyfus debate. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solymosi, T., & Shook, J. (Eds.). (2014). Neuroscience, neurophilosophy and pragmatism. Brains at work with the world. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spurrett, D., & Cowley, S. (2010). The extended infant: Utterance-activity and distributed cognition. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 295–323). Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, P. (2008). Délocaliser les phénomènes mentaux: La philosophie de l’esprit de Dewey. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 62(245, 3), 273–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, P. (2014). Enacting anti-representationalism. The scope and the limits of enactive critiques of representationalism. Avant, 5(2), 43–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, P. (2017). Pragmatism in cognitive science: From the pragmatic turn to Deweyan adverbialism. Pragmatism Today, 8(1), 9–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, D. (1985). The interpersonal world of the infant. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trevarthen, C. (1979). Communication and cooperation in early infancy: A description of primary intersubjectivity. In M. Bullowa (Ed.), Before speech. The beginning of interpersonal communication (pp. 321–348). London: Cambridge U.P.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2013). Mindedness, mindlessness and first-person authority. In J. K. Schear (Ed.), Mind, reason, and being-in-the-world: The McDowell-Dreyfus debate (pp. 320–340). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roberta Dreon.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dreon, R. Framing cognition: Dewey’s potential contributions to some enactivist issues. Synthese 198 (Suppl 1), 485–506 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02212-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02212-x

Keywords

Navigation